THE INTUITIONS OF THE MIND INDUCTIVELY INVESTIGATED. BY THE REY. JAMES M‘COSH, LL.D., PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN QUEEN’S COLLEGE, BELFAST, AUTHOR OF ‘THE METHOD OF THE DIVINE GOVERNMENT PHYSICAL AND MORAL/ AND JOINT AUTHOR OF ‘TYPICAL FORMS AND SPECIAL ENDS IN CREATION.* NEW YORK: ROBERT CARTER AND BROTHERS, 530, BROADWAY. 1860. CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION. Page Aim of the Work and Method of Inquiry 1 $art jFtrst GENERAL VIEW OP THE NATURE OF THE INTUITIVE CONVICTIONS OF THE MIND. BOOK I. GENERAL PROPOSITIONS REGARDING INTUITIONS. CHAPTER I. NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS. Sect. I. No Innate Mental Images or Representations .... 13 Sect. II. No Innate, Abstract, or General Notions 16 Sect. III. No A Priori Forms imposed by the Mind on Objects 19 Sect. IV. The Intuitions are not immediately before Conscious- ness as Laws or Principles 21 CHAPTER II. Sect. I. There are Intuitive Principles operating in the Mind . 23 Sect. II. The Native Convictions of the Mind are of the Nature of Perceptions or Intuitions 29 Sect. III. Intuitive Convictions rise on the Contemplation of Ob- jects presented or represented to the Mind 30 POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. IV Page Sect. IV. The Intuitions of the Mind are primarily directed to Individual Objects 31 Sect. Y. The Individual Intuitive Convictions can be generalized into Maxims, and these are entitled to be represented as Phi- losophic Principles 33 CONTENTS. BOOK II. CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS AND METHOD OF EMPLOYING THEM. CHAPTER I. MARKS AND PECULIARITIES OF INTUITIONS. Sect. I. Tests 37 Sect. II. Different Aspects of Intuitions, and their Theoretical Characters 41 Sect. III. Certain Misapprehensions in regard to the Character of Intuitive Convictions 55 Sect. IY. Certain Practical Characteristics 59 CHAPTER II. METHOD OP EMPLOYING INTUITIVE PRINCIPLES. Sect. I. The Spontaneous and Reflex Use of Intuitive Principles 62 Sect. II. Sources of Error in Metaphysical Speculation . . , 69 Sect. III. Conditions of the Legitimacy of the Appeal to Intuitive Principles 76 Sect. IY. Method of Investigating and Interpreting our Intui- tions 85 Sect. Y. What Explanation can be given of the Intuitions of the Mind ’ 92 (SUPPLEMENTARY.) BRIEF CRITICAL REVIEW OF OPI- NIONS IN REGARD TO INTUITIVE TRUTHS ..... 98 CHAPTER III. CONTENTS. V $art $ecmttu PARTICULAR EXAMINATION OF THE INTUITIONS. BOOK I. PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. CHAPTEE I. BODY AND SPIRIT. Page Sect. I. The Mind begins its Intelligent Acts with Knowledge. The Simple Cognitive Powers 119 Sect. II. Our Intuitive Cognitions of Body 122 Sect. III. Some Distinctions to be attended to in regard to our Cognition of Body 133 Sect. IY. The Qualities of Matter known by Intuition .... 145 Sect. Y. Our Intuitive Cognition of Self or of Spirit 148 CHAPTEE II. ANALYSIS OF OUR PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. Sect. I. (Preliminary.) On the Nature of Abstraction and Gene- ralization 157 Sect. II. On Being 161 Sect. III. On Substance . . . . v 164 Sect. IY. On Mode, Quality, Property, Essence 173 Sect. Y. On Personality 180 Sect. YI. On Extension 183 Sect. YII. On Number 184 Sect. YIII. On Motion 185 Sect. IX. On Power 187 Sect. X. (Supplementary.) The Various Kinds of Power known by Experience 187 BOOK II. PRIMITIVE BELIEFS. CHAPTEE I. Theib General Nature 196 VI CONTENTS. Page CHAPTER II. Time and Space 202 CHAPTER III. The Infinite 214 CHAPTER IV. The Extent, Tests, and Power of our Native Beliefs . 231 BOOK III. CHAPTER I. TiiEiit General Nature, and a Classification of them . 236 CHAPTER II. RELATIONS INTUITIVELY OBSERVED BY THE MIND. Sect. I. Relation of Identity 242 Sect. II. Relation of Whole and Parts . . 247 Sect. III. Relations of Space 250 Sect. IV. The Relations of Time 252 Sect. V. The Relations of Quantity 252 Sect. VI. The Relations of Resemblance 255 Sect. VII. Relations of Active Property 257 Sect. VIII. Relation of Cause and Effect 258 PRIMITIVE JUDGMENTS. BOOK IV. MORAL CONVICTIONS. CHAPTER I. GENERAL VIEW OF THE MOTIVE AND MORAL POWERS. Sect. I. The Appetencies, the Will, and the Conscience . . . 279 Sect. II. {Supplementary.) On the Beautiful 288 CHAPTER II. CONVICTIONS INVOLVED IN THE EXERCISES OP CONSCIENCE. Sect. I. Convictions as to the Nature of Moral Good .... 290 Sect. II. On Sin and Error 297 Sect. III. Relation of Moral Good and Happiness 302 CONTENTS. VII Page CHAPTER III. The Freedom of the "Will 308 $art Efjtrtc INTUITIVE PRINCIPLES AND THE VARIOUS SCIENCES. BOOK I. METAPHYSICS. CHAPTER I. Metaphysics, Gnosiology, and Ontology 315 CHAPTER II. GNOSIOLOGY. Sect. I. On Knowledge 322 Sect. II. On tlie Origin of our Knowledge and Ideas .... 326 Sect. III. Limits to our Knowledge, Ideas, and Beliefs .... 334 Sect. IY. Relation of Intuition and Experience 340 Sect. Y. On tlie Necessity attached to our Primary Convictions . 345 Sect. YI. {Supplementary?) On the Distinctions between the Un- derstanding and the Reason ; between a priori and a posteriori Principles; between Form and Matter; between Subjective and Objective; between the Logical and Chronological Order of Ideas; between the Cause and Occasion of Innate Ideas . . 351 CHAPTER III. ONTOLOGY. Sect. I. On Knowing and Being 358 Sect. II. On Idealism 362 Sect. III. On Scepticism 374 Sect. IV. On the Conditioned and the Unconditioned .... 385 Sect. V. (Supplementary.) The Antinomies of Kant 388 Sect. YI. (Supplementary.) Examination of Mr. J. S. Mill’s Me- taphysical System 390 VIII CONTENTS. METAPHYSICAL PRINCIPLES INVOLVED IN THE SCIENCES. BOOK II. CHAPTER I. Page Distinction between the Demonstrative or Formal and the Material or Inductive Sciences ........ 395 CHAPTER II. THE MENTAL SCIENCES. Sect. I. Classification of the Mental Sciences 400 Sect. II. Logic 402 Sect. III. Ethics 406 CHAPTER III. Mathematics 409 CHAPTER IV. Intuitive Principles involved in the Physical Sciences 415 CHAPTER Y. APPLICATION TO THEOLOGY. Sect. I. Faith and Reason 419 Sect. II. Natural Theology. The Theistic Argument .... 427 Sect. III. On the Immortality of the Soul 441 Sect. IY. Pantheism 446 Sect. Y. Christian Divinity 461 Sect. YI. Man as a Religious Being 476 Sect. YII. Rational Theology 480 Sect. VIII. Intuitional Theology 482 ERRATA. Page 166, line 5 from foot, for “ Abriei” read “ Ulrici.” Page 246, line 7 from head, for “ A is not A ” read “ A is not Not-A.” INTUITIONS OF THE MIND. INTRODUCTION. AIM OF THE WORE AND METHOD OF INQUIRY. According to one class of speculators, the mind derives all its knowledge, judgments, maxims, from observation and experience. According to another class of thinkers, there are ideas, truths, principles, which originate in the native power, and are seen in the inward light of the mind. These last have been called by a great number of names, such as innate ideas, intuitions, necessary judgments, fundamental laws of belief, principles of common sense, first or primitive truths; and diverse have been the accounts given of them, and the uses to which they have been turned. This is a controversy which has been from the beginning, and which is ever being renewed in one form or other. It appears to me that this contest is now, and has ever been, characterized by an immense complication of confusion; and confusion, as Bacon has remarked, is more difficult to rectify than open error. I am not, in this treatise, to plunge at once into a thicket, in which so many have lost themselves as they sought to find or cut a way through it. But my aim throughout is to ascertain what are the actual laws or principles in the mind denoted by these various 2 INTRODUCTION. phrases, what is their mode of operation, what the rule which they follow, and the purpose which they are com- petent to serve. As the result, it will appear that there are in the mind such existences and powers as primary perceptions and fundamental laws of belief, but that they are very different in their nature from the account which is often given of them, and that they are by no means fitted to accomplish the ends to which they have been turned in metaphysical and theological speculation. I would as soon believe that there are no such agents as heat, che- mical affinity, and electricity in physical nature, as that there are no immediate perceptions and native-born con- victions in this mind of ours. I look indeed on the one kind of agents, like the other, to be among the deepest and most potent at work in this world, mental and ma- terial ; and yet the one class, like the other, while ope- rating every instant on soul or body, are apt to hide themselves from the view. Indeed they discover them- selves only by their effects, and their law can be de- tected only by a careful observation of its actings; and it should be added, that both are capable of evil as well as good, and are to be carefully watched and guarded in the use which is made of them. The prejudice against native and necessary principles has arisen to a great extent from the extravagant account which has been rendered of them, and from the vain, the ambitious, and often pernicious purposes which they have been made to serve. It is to be hoped, that by a clear determination of their exact nature, and of the rules of their operation, and by a judicious exposition of the me- thod by which alone they can be discovered, and of the restrictions which should be laid on their employment, the feeling against them on the part of so many, philo- sophers and non-philosophers, may be dispelled; while INTRODUCTION. 3 at the same time rash speculators are prevented from em- ploying them for the furthering of pretentious ends to which they have no legitimate reference. In inquiring into the evidence of their existence, into the place which they hold in the constitution of the mind, the laws by which they are guided, and the way in which they manifest themselves, I am to proceed throughout in the Method of Induction. I profess to prosecute the investigation in the way of the observation of facts—with an accompanying analysis and co-ordination, but still of facts, which have been carefully observed. It has often been shown that the method of induction admits, mutatis mutandis, of an application to the study of the human mind, as well as to that of the material universe. The difference in the application lies mainly in this, that in the one case we use self-consciousness, or the internal sense, whereas in the other we employ the external sense as the organ or instrument. I certainly do not propose to find out the intuitions of the mind by the bodily eye, aided or unaided by the microscope, nor discover their mode of operation by the blowpipe. They are in their nature spiritual, and so sense cannot touch them, nor see them, nor hear them, nor can the telescope in its widest range detect them. Still they are there in our mental nature; there is an eye of wider sweep than the telescope, and more searching than the microscope, ready to be directed towards them. By introspection we may look on them in operation; by abstraction or analysis we may separate the essential peculiarity from the rough concrete presentations; and by generalization, rise to the law which they follow. But let me not be misunderstood. The method pur- sued, as it is not on the one hand to be confounded with an ambitious transcendentalism which declines to ask help from observation, so it is as little on the other hand 4 INTRODUCTION. to be identified with a miserable sensational empiricism. I do not expect to discover what are the native princi- ples of the mind by a priori speculation, but neither do I profess by observation to lay or construct a foundation on which to rear fundamental truth. I am not, there- fore, to be lightly charged with a contradiction, as if I resorted to experience for a basis or ground of principles which I represent as original and independent. I em- ploy induction simply as a mean or method of finding laws which are prior to induction, otherwise induction could not find them. Experience is not supposed by me to furnish the ground of necessary truth; all that it can do is to supply the facts which enable us to discover the truth, and that the truth is necessary. I allude to this objection, not with the view of formally meeting it here, but in order to show that it has not been overlooked, and then adjourn the discussion of it to its appropriate place. It will come out, in the course of our survey, that while there are regulative principles in the mind, operating al- together independently of any reflex notice we may take of them, arid not depending for their authority on our induction of them, it is at the same time true that they can become known to us as general principles only by inward observation, and can be legitimately employed in philosophic speculation only on the condition of being rigidly inducted. By observation we may rise to the discovery of mental principles which do not in themselves depend on observation, but which have a place in our constitution anterior to our observation of them, and are there, as observation discovers, native, necessary, and uni- versal. In some respects, it is an unfortunate time for giving forth such a work to the world. Every age, like the seed, is at one and the same time the product of combined in- fluences in the past, and the germ of life for the future. INTRODUCTION. 5 In this present age, two manner of principles, each of the character of a different parent, are struggling for the mastery; the one earth-born, sensational, empirical, utili- tarian, deriving all ideas from the senses, and all know- able truth from man's limited experience, and holding that man can be swayed by no motives of a higher order than the wish to secure pleasure or avoid pain; the other, if not heaven-bom, at least cloud-born, being ideal, tran- scendental, pantheistic, attributing man's loftiest ideas to an inward light, appealing to principles which are dis- covered without the trouble of observation, and issuing in a belief in the good, instead of a belief in God. Each of these views has its keen partisans, either violently at- tacking one another, or regarding each other with silent contempt, while the great body of reading men are pro- fessedly indifferent,—those who claim to be neutral, how- ever, being all the while unconsciously in the service either of the one or other, commonly of the lower or earthly, just as those who profess to belong neither to God nor Mammon, do in fact belong to Mammon. What then can be expected of the reception of such a work in such an age ? A large body, even of the think- ing portion of the community, are prejudiced against all such discussions, as fruitless of good in every cir- cumstance, and in some forms productive of mischief. I suspect the great mass of those who call themselves prac- tical men, and the majority of those addicted to the study of the physical sciences, will be further prepossessed against this treatise as defending a doctrine which they thought had been long ago and for ever exploded by Locke. On the other hand, those most inclined to favour such pursuits are, for the most part, committed and pledged to extreme views, and can scarcely be expected to look with a favourable eye on a work which, pro- fessedly built on pure observation, declines to follow any 6 INTRODUCTION. school,—indeed, proclaims that as schools and sects, with their separate standpoints and watchwords, have long ago ceased in physical science, so it is time they should disappear in the field of mental science likewise; that those who prosecute the study, calling no man master, may look, without prepossession, into the volume spread out before them in their own soul, and read it with the eye of consciousness. Nearly all confessed metaphysi- cians will assert that I am degrading high philosophy in making it submit to the method of induction, and that the restrictions which I would lay upon speculation must deprive it of its most fascinating charms ; while hundreds of eager youths, walking hopefully on the high a priori road, and expecting that the next turn—which they al- ready see not far in front—must open on the great ocean of absolute truth, will feel as if they were unmercifully stopped and turned back at the very time when the long looked-for scene was about to burst gloriously on their view. But regarded under some other aspects, this is an age in which such a work (I would on this account as well as many others it were only worthy of its subject) is espe- cially needed. Every nation awakened to intelligence must have a philosophy of some description. Whatever men may profess or affect, they cannot in fact do without it; and if any age or nation, arrived at civilization, will not form or adopt a high and elevating philosophy, it will assuredly fall under the power of a low and a debasing one. It oftens happens that a profession of contempt for all metaphysics as being futile and unintelligible, is often an introduction to a discussion which is metaphy- sical without the parties knowing it (as the person in the Erench play had spoken prose all his life without being aware of it); and of such metaphysics it will com- monly be found that they are futile and unintelligible INTRODUCTION. 7 enough. Often is Aristotle denounced in language bor- rowed from himself, and the Schoolmen are disparaged by those who are all the while using distinctions which they have cut with sharp chisel in the rock, never to be effaced. There are persons speaking with contempt of Plato, Des- cartes, Locke, and all the metaphysicians who are taking advantage of the great truths which they have discovered. I could easily show that in our very sermons from the pulpit, and orations in the senate, and pleadings at the bar, principles are ever and anon appealed to which have come from the heads of our deepest thinkers, in ages long gone by, and who may now be forgotten by all but a few antiquarians in philosophy. Natural science itself is, in the hands of its most advanced votaries, ever touching on the borders of metaphysics, and compelling our physicists to rest on certain fundamental convictions as to exten- sion and force. The truth is, in very proportion as ma- terial science advances, do thinking minds feel the need of something to go down deeper and mount up higher than the senses can do—of some means of settling those anxious questions which the mind is ever putting in re- gard to the soul, and the relation of the universe to God, and of a foundation on which the understanding can ultimately and confidently repose. Whatever the super- ficial may think, philosophy is an underlying power, of vast importance because of mighty influence. It is be- cause it is fundamental and radical, that it is unseen by the vulgar, who notice only what is above the surface. Let us see that the foundation be well laid, that the root be properly planted. That foundation must be secure which is founded in our mental constitution; that is the proper root which is planted by our Maker. In. determining the precise nature of the mental intui- tions, we may hope to be able to settle what they can do, and, as no less important, what they cannot do. Thus do 8 INTRODUCTION. I hope to contribute my little aid in elevating the low, and in bringing down the presumptuous tendencies of the age; thus would I raise the downward, and at the same time lower the proud look; thus would I keep men from poring ever on the dust of the earth on the one hand, and on the other hand from attempting, Icarus-like, to mount in a flight which must issue in a lamentable fall. Thus would I seek to raise the view-position of some reckoned by themselves and others the wiser and more sober, who are digging for ever in the mere clay of ma- terial existence, and who, believing in nothing but what can be seen and touched, never rise to the contemplation of moral and spiritual, of immutable and eternal truth; and thus too would I save the more promising of our intellectual youths from falling under the power of a boasting a priori intuitionalism, which is alluring them on by gilded clouds, which will turn out to be damp and chill after they have taken infinite pains to climb to them and to enter them. In Germany, in Britain, in the United States of Ame- rica,—alas! France, with its finest minds ground down by a military despotism necessitated by an unprincipled democracy, has ceased to be a country of independent thought, and so cannot be named in such a connection, —thought is in a transition, and therefore a very restless state. In Germany, the high transcendental, intuitional, or dialectic method, has wrought itself out—has cropped out to the surface in thinness and brittleness ; and in the reaction, eminent professors are lecturing to half-empty benches; and books which if published twenty years ago would have moved thought to its greatest depths, can now find little sale, few readers, and scarcely any believers; while in the absence of a judicious philosophy, accepted and influential, a plausible materialism, acknowledging no existence but matter and force, is making consider- INTRODUCTION. 9 able progress on the pretence of furnishing what the old metaphysics never yielded, something tangible and there- fore solid. In the English-speaking nations there coexists with the old experiential spirit engendered by Locke, and the sensational spirit imported from France, a deter- mined recoil, especially among certain musing and impul- sive youths, against Lockism, and sensationalism, and the bony and haggard forms of physicism, which have be- come denuded of all truth, intellectual, moral, and religi- ous, transcending sense and experience; and there is strong tendency towards an idealism, which, all decked and ra- diant, is seeking to win them to its embrace. It is surely possible that there may be some disturbed by the din of these controversies, and shunning both extremes, who may be prepared to welcome an attempt to discover—not, certainly, all truth (which is precluded to the human mind), but, by a sure method—that of observation and facts—a sure foundation, laid by God himself, and on which other truths may be laid, and on which they may firmly rest. I would not have taken such pains (as I can say con- scientiously I have done) with this treatise, had I not been persuaded that it embodies important truth. At the same time I feel that in discussing so many and such abstruse topics, confusion and error may have crept in. My conviction indeed is very strong as to the accuracy of the general views unfolded in the First and Third of the three Parts into which the work is divided. There is more room for doubt and hesitation as to the discus- sions on the more particular topics in the Second Part. In regard to these, I would not only give—what indeed I know I cannot withhold—full freedom to others to differ from me, but I reserve to myself the right to improve, to modify, to correct, if need be, the views here set forth, should I receive new light on further reading and reflec- 10 INTRODUCTION. tion. I make this admission and claim this prerogative the more readily, as in doing so I may be in the better position to maintain that oversights and errors in these details will not be found after all to affect the general principles expounded in this volume, and their applica- tion to every form of speculation, philosophic and reli- gious. Note.—In thinking out this Work, I have made free but not unacknowledged use of the works of the great thinkers, both of ancient and modern times, both of the Continent and of Britain, who have pondered on these topics. Among later metaphysicians I have specially to acknowledge my obligations to the erudition, the unsur- passed logical power, and the profound observation, of the late Sir William Hamilton. I have also derived ad- vantage, in the discussion of certain points, from the wri- tings of living authors, British and Continental, who will be quoted or referred to at the proper places. In ma- king this acknowledgment, I do not profess to belong to the school of any eminent man of the past or present, nor to any school, except the one which will attend to nothing but facts. 1 claim to have so far caught the spirit of those who have gone before, as to be resolute to maintain my independence, and I have not scrupled to state wherein I differ from those whose writings have yielded me the most valuable thoughts and suggestions. I have so constructed the work as to put incidental discussions and criticisms in Chapters and Sections, Pre- liminary and Supplemental, printed in smaller type. PART FIRST. GENERAL VIEW OF THE NATURE OF THE INTUITIVE CONVICTIONS OF THE MIND. 13 BOOK I. GENERAL PROPOSITIONS REGARDING INTUITIONS. CHAPTER I. NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS. Sect. I. No Innate Mental Images or Represntations. The mind of man has the power of imaging or repre- senting, in old forms by the memory, or in new forms by the imagination, whatever it has at any time known or experienced. To this mental property the Aristotelian phrase ‘phantasy,’ in use till last century, and revived of late by Sir William Hamilton,* might be appropriately ap- plied, and then we should have the old term * phantasm ’ (not * phantom,’ which might continue to denote the spec- tre) ready to designate the mental result, or the idea in consciousness. Having seen a given mountain, I can recall it at any time. Not only so, but I can put what I have experienced in an indefinite number of new shapes and colours. Having seen Mont Blanc, I can, when it pleases me, bring it up before me in all its bulk, supported by its snow-capped buttresses and flanked by its glancing glaciers; but I can do more, I can picture a mountain covered, not with ice, but with silver, or a mountain * See his edition of Reid’s Works, p. 291. 14 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. reaching up to the moon. I can reproduce in like mode whatever has been brought under my notice by any of the other senses. I can recall and reconstruct the bodily sensations,—the sounds, the colours, the tastes,—which I have at any time experienced. Milton, when he wrote ‘ Paradise Lost,’ had lost the power of beholding colours, but he had still the capacity of imaging them to him- self, or delineating them to others, as he did in his pic- ture of the garden of Eden. A late distinguished poet never had the sense of smell, except for one brief but enjoyable space, when it awoke as he stood in a garden with flowers; but he must have been able ever after to realize what odours meant. It is to be carefully noted that this reproductive power reaches not only over all that has been acquired by the bodily senses, but over all that has been obtained by consciousness or the in- ward sense. I can recall the joys, the hopes, the sorrows, the fears, which at some former time may have moved my bosom. I can do more : I can picture myself, or picture others, in new and unheard-of scenes of gladness or of grief. Not only can I represent to myself the counte- nance of my friend, I can have an idea of his character and dispositions. I can form a mental picture of the out- ward scenes in which Shakspeare or Walter Scott place their heroes or heroines; but I can also enter into their thoughts and feelings. But all these ideas, in the sense of phantasms, are re- productions of past experience in old forms or new dis- positions. He who has had the use of his eyes at any time, can ever after understand what is meant by the colour of scarlet, but the person born blind has not the most distant idea of it in the sense of image, and if pressed for an answer to the question what he supposes it to be, he can come no nearer the reality than the man mentioned by Locke, who likened it to the sound of a NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS. 15 trumpet; or than the blind boy of whom I have heard, who when asked whether he would prefer a lilac-coloured or a brown-coloured book, offered as a prize, decided for the lilac, as he supposed it must resemble the lilac-bush, whose odour had been so agreeable to him. Having experience of cogitations and sentiments of our own, we apprehend and appreciate those of others. Having a spiritual nature ourselves, we can form some idea of that Great Spirit in whose image we can claim to have been fashioned. But there may be attributes possessed by God of which we can form as little idea as the deaf man can of sounds, or the man without smell can of odours; they may be attributes to which we possess nothing like, and which we may be incapable of representing even in imagination. Niebuhr, the traveller, had often brought before him in his old-age the scenes of Eastern lands, but it was because he had witnessed them in his youth ; and even we who have never been in those countries can so far understand the descriptions in his travels, because we have had the elements of them in our own experience ; but there may be scenes in heaven which it hath not en- tered into the heart of man to conceive, inasmuch as no- thing similar has passed under his notice in this lower world. Now the proposition advanced in this Section is that the soul is not born unto this world with a stock of such phantasms, ready to come out on occasions presented. I rather think that this is the sense in which the phrase is understood by those who give Locke the credit of exploding the doctrine of “innate ideas” for ever. Taking * idea ’ in the sense of ‘ image,’ they say, what can be so unreasonable as to suppose that the mind comes into the world with such impressions ready to start forth, like writing with invisible ink, or like sun-pictures when exposed to certain chemical agencies. Locke, who 16 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. I suspect took ‘ idea’ very much in the sense of mental image, or representation, may very possibly claim to have for ever set aside this view. But his credit in this respect is not very great after all. "For I rather think no philo- sopher of influence ever propounded such a doctrine, for- mally or explicitly. It is quite conceivable, indeed, that Plato might have consistently held some such doctrine. He might have maintained that the soul did come into the world with such ideas; but then he would have as- cribed them to experience acquired in a previous state of existence. But Plato’s doctrine of ideas, while I believe it, in many aspects of it, to be as true as it is sublime, is apt to run into myths and fancies in the expression, so that it is difficult to give a thoroughly consistent ex- position of it. By c idea ’ he meant a pattern in or before the Divine Mind from all eternity; and he supposes a course of philosophic abstraction to be quite as neces- sary as reminiscence to call up such ideas into conscious- ness. But whether the view which I am opposing has or has not been entertained by men of eminence, it is expe- dient to notice it, in order at the very commencement to remove it out of the way as an encumbrance. Sect. II. No Innate Abstract or General Notions. This proposition is not the same as that illustrated in last Section. A mental picture of a mountain is one thing, and a general notion of the class mountain is a very different thing. All our cognitions by the senses or the consciousness, and all our subsequent images of them in memory or imagination, are singular and concrete; that is, they are of individual things, and of things with an aggregate of qualities. I can see or picture to myself an individual man of a certain form or character, but I cannot perceive nor adequately represent in the phantasy the class man. I can see or imagine a piece of magne- NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS. 17 tized iron, but I cannot see or imagine the polarity of the iron apart from the iron. Still the mind has the high capacity of forming ab- stract and general notions. Out of the concrete it can form the abstract notion. I can see or image a lily only as with both a shape and colour, but I can in thought contemplate its whiteness apart from its form. Having seen a number of beasts with four limbs, I can think about a class of animals agreeing in this, that they are all quadrupeds. It appears then that the mental image and the abstract or general notion are not the same. The former is an exercise of the reproductive powers, recall- ing the old or putting the old in new collocations. The other is the result of an exercise of thought, separating the part from the whole, or contemplating an indefinite number of objects as possessing common qualities. If the one may be called the phantasm; the other, in con- tradistinction, may be denominated the notion or concept; or, to designate it more unequivocally, the logical notion or concept. But it is quite as true of the abstract and general no- tions, as of the mental representations of the individual, that they are not in the soul when it comes into the world. It has been the avowed doctrine of the great body of philosophers, that the mind starts with the sin- gular and the concrete. All our abstract notions are the result of a process in which we separate in thought the part from the whole; say the quality, from the substance presenting itself with its qualities,—say transparency, con- templated apart from the transparent ice or glass. All our general notions are the product of a process in which we contemplate objects as possessing common attributes, —say philosophers, as men agreeing in this, that they are seekers of wisdom. It is, as I reckon it, the true merit of Locke that, in 18 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. the second book of his Essay on the Human Under- standing, he shows how in the ideas we form of such ob- jects as space, time, substance, cause, and infinity, and in the general maxims employed in speculation, such as that “ it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time,” there is involved a process of the un- derstanding founded on a previous experience.* It will be acknowledged that the soul is not born into the world with such abstract ideas as those of hardness, or organic action, or life, nor such general notions as those of mine- ral, plant, animal. This is admitted by all. But it is equally true that the soul of the infant has not yet in an abstract or general form those ideas which certain meta- * Wherein lie the defects of Locke will come out as we advance (see more especially Part I. Book II. Chap. III., and Part III. Book I. Chap. II., sect, ii.); but I think he is invincible when he shows that chil- dren do not start with general maxims consciously before them, and that savages are not in possession of them. Thus, speaking of the maxim, “It is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be,” he says, “ A great part of illiterate people and savages pass many years of their rational age without ever thinking on this and the like general propositions ” (Essay, bk. i. ch. xi. s. 12). “ There is no knowledge of these general and self- evident maxims in the mind till it comes to the exercise of reason ” (ib., s. 14). Speaking of more particular self-evident propositions, which are assented to at first hearing, as that one and two are equal to three, he says, “ They are known and assented to by those who are utterly ig- norant of these more general maxims, and so being earlier in the mind than those (as they are called) first principles, cannot owe to them the assent wherewith they are received at first hearing ” (s. 20). “ For though a child quickly assents to this proposition, that an apple is not fire, when lie has got the ideas of these two different things distinctly im- printed on his mind, and has learned that the names apple and fire stand for them, yet it will be some years after, before the same child will assent to this proposition, that it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be” (s. 23). “He that will say children join these general abstract speculations with their sucking-bottles and their rat- tles, may perhaps with justice be thought to have more passion and zeal for his opinion, but less sincerity and truth, than one of that age” (s. 25). “Such kind of general propositions are seldom men- tioned in the huts of Indians ; much less are they found in the thoughts of children, or any impressions of them on the minds of naturals ” (s. 27). NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS. 19 physicians describe as innate, as those of the ego and the non-ego, extension and potency, mind and matter, cause and effect, infinity and moral good. We reach the ab- stract idea of hardness by specially fixing the attention on one of the qualities of body. In like manner it is ne- cessary, in order to attain the idea of space, to separate in thought the space from body known as occupying space. We get the idea of bodily substance by consider- ing the permanent being apart from that which changes in the bodies falling under our notice. It is one of the aims of this treatise to specify the way in which the mind gets these ideas in the concrete and singular. But for the present I am seeking to have rubbish removed, that there may be free space whereon to lay a foundation. And I think it of vast moment to have it admitted that every abstract notion implies a process of separation, that every general notion implies a process of comparison, and that both one and other proceed on a previous know- ledge which has come within the range of our conscious- ness. Sect. III. No a psiosi Forms imposed by the Mind on Objects. This proposition is laid down in opposition to a view which has been extensively and resolutely entertained of late years. Traces of it in a looser form may be detected at a much earlier date, but it may be regarded as for- mally introduced into philosophy by Kant, in his great work on the Kritick of Pure Reason. Suppose that the eyes, in every exercise of vision, were to start with a lens of a particular shape and colour, every object seen would take a predetermined form, and appear in a special hue. It is thus, according to Kant, that the mind sets out with certain forms which it imposes on phenomena,—that is, on appearances presenting themselves. In every pri- 20 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. mary cognition the mind imposes two Forms, one of Space and another of Time, on the phenomena presented empi- rically or a posteriori. Again, in comparing its cogni- tions, it sets them in a number of frameworks, called Categories, such as that of Quantity, Quality, Relation (including Substance and Accident, Causality and Depen- dence), and Modality, which have a reality not objectively in things but subjectively in the mind. A yet higher for- mative power brings these categories into unity in three Ideas of Pure Reason, those of Substance, Interdepend- ence of Phenomena, and God, in which all objective re- ality has disappeared. These forms of the senses, cate- gories of the understanding, and ideas of pure reason, constitute the a priori as distinguished from the a poste- riori elements in the mental exercises. It would carry us prematurely into very deep topics, with very ramified connections, were I at this early stage to criticize this doctrine in all its extent and bearings. It must suffice for the present to affirm that so far as it declares that the mind in cognition gives to the object what is not in the object, it is an unnatural doctrine, and is fraught with far-reaching consequences of a perilous character. The doctrine which I hope to establish is that the intuitive or cognitive powers do not impose forms on the objects, but are simply the agents or instru- ments by which we are enabled to discover what is in the objects. The mind, in looking at a material object, does not superinduce extension on it, but it observes that it is in space and must be in space. It does not carry within it a chain wherewith to connect events by a law of causation, but it has a capacity to discover that events are so connected and must be so connected. The capa- city of cognition in the mind is not that of the bent mirror, to reflect the object under modified forms, but of the plane mirror, to reflect it as it is in its proper shape NEGATIVE PROPOSITIONS. 21 and colour. The truth is perceived by the mind, not formed; it is cognized, and not created. There must of course be a correspondence between the subject, mind, and the object, material or mental, contemplated; but it is a correspondence whereby the one knows and the other is known. This seems to me to be our natural, intuitive, and necessary conviction, and he who departs from it is landed in thickening difficulties on every side, and in particular cannot possibly defend himself from the assaults of scepticism; for if the mind can in respect of what it apprehends in the object create so much, why not suppose that it creates all ? If it can create the space in which the object is perceived, why not suppose that it can create the object itself? This was the conclusion drawn by Fichte, who, carrying out the principles of Kant a step further, made the whole supposed external object a mere projection of the mind. There is no satisfactory or consistent way of avoiding this consequence but by adhering to the natural doctrine, and holding that the mind is so constituted as to know the object as it is, un- der the aspects in which it is presented to it. Sect. IV. The Intuitions are not immediately before Consciousness as Laws or Principles. I am to labour to show, in coming Sections, that there are intuitive principles in the mind regulating cognitions, beliefs, and judgments, whether intellectual or moral. My present position is, that operating in the mind as native laws or rules, they are not, as such, before the conscious- ness. Every one speaks of there being in the mind capacities, powers, or faculties, such as the memory, or the imagina- tion, or the reason, yet no one is immediately conscious of these mental powers. We are conscious of remembering a given event, of imagining a given scene, of discovering 22 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. a given relation, but not of the mental power from which the acts proceed. Such considerations show that there may be operating in the mind faculties which do not fall directly under the internal eye. What is true of the facul- ties is true of the intuitive potencies of the mind. In- deed the intuitive principles of the mind are very closely related to the faculties. I have seldom however seen the precise relation between them distinctly pointed out. One class of investigators, such as Locke, treat of the faculties; another class, such as the German metaphysi- cians who have ramified from Kant, of a priori principles in the mind; while a third class, such as the Scottish school wdiich has sprung from Reid, admit both into their system, but without explaining their connection. To me it appears that the intuitive or necessary principles of the mind are just the fundamental principles or regula- tive laws of the faculties. But without dwelling on this at present, it is enough to announce that the necessary principles, like the faculties of the mind, do not come immediately under the cognizance of consciousness. The individual actings do indeed fall directly under reflection or the internal sense. Thus we are conscious that the mind, on discovering a given effect, judges and decides that it must have a cause, and looks for a cause ; but it has not meanwhile before it the general principle that every effect has a cause, or the principle of causation expressly formalized. Being convinced that we exist, we cannot be made to believe that w7e do not exist; but this is not because we have consciously before us the principle of contradiction, ‘ that it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time.’ It will be shown forthwith that we arrive reflexly at a know- ledge of the intuitive principle, which operates spontane- ously, by the observation and generalization of its in- dividual acts or energies. My present purpose is gained POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. 23 if it is shown that such metaphysical principles as causation and contradiction are not directly before con- sciousness as rules, laws, or principles. CHAPTER II. POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. Sect. I. There are Intuitive Principles operating in the Mind. I do not propose to bring a full or satisfactory proof of this assertion in this short Section; the evidence will be found in the Second Part, in which our intuitive con- victions are unfolded and discussed in detail. All that I profess to do at this stage is, to announce and explain cer- tain positions which I hope to establish as we proceed, and answer some preliminary objections which are likely to occur to the English reader. To illustrate my meaning I must refer to certain convictions which I suppose to be intuitive, such as those regarding Space and Time, Sub- stance, Quality, Cause and Effect, and Moral Good; all of these will be treated in detail in subsequent parts of the volume. (1.) The first position I would lay down is that the mind must have something native or innate. The word innate is apt to be obnoxious to English ears; it is as- sociated with views which Locke is supposed to have set aside for ever; and the revival of it will appear to some like the raising of a carcase from the grave to which it had been happily consigned. I have no partiality for a 24 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. phrase which has been employed to set forth doctrines which it will be one object of this Work to undermine. To the phrase * innate ideas ’ I take strong objections, which will come out as we advance. To the term ‘ innate,’ if it were employed to qualify the proper noun, I see no objections; but if any are offended with it, the word ‘ native ’ will serve our purpose as well. All that either phrase denotes is, that there is something—at present I do not say what—in man’s soul at the time it is born. In this respect it is like the bodily substances which fall under our notice. These bodies are something and have something. This piece of iron which I hold in my hand is not a nonentity; it is an existence; it occupies space; it resists pressure; it has a colour. The soul of man is also an existence; it knows ; it understands ; it grieves; it rejoices. The capacity which it has of doing so may be described as native and original. In this respect it is like the bodily frame when it comes forth from the womb. That body is not all which it is afterwards to become. Yet it is not, even at this early stage, a nonentity; it is not a nothing about to grow into something. Already that frame has a struc- ture, a form, and most wondrous properties. And just as little is the soul, when it awakes to consciousness, a nonentity; even at this point, it is an existence, a some- thing, and is possessed of something which may be called innate or connate. Even on the supposition that it is like a surface of wax or a sheet of white paper, ready to receive whatever is im- pressed or written on it, it must have something inborn. If the mind have but a power of impressibility, it has in this something innate. The very wax and paper, in the inadequate illustration referred to, have capabilities, the capacity of taking something on them, and retaining it. But such comparisons have all a misleading tendency. POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. 25 Surely the mind has something more than a mere recep- tivity ! It is not a mere surface, on which matter may reflect itself as on a mirror: our consciousness testifies that, in comparison with matter, it is active; that it has an original, and an originating potency. (2.) A second position may be maintained; that this something has rules, laws, or properties. Matter, with all its endowments, inorganic and organic, is regulated by laws which it is the office of physical and physiological science to discover. All the powers or properties of ma- terial substance have rules of action ; for example, gravi- tation and chemical affinity have regulations which can be expressed in quantitative proportions. That mind also has properties, is shown by its action; and surely these properties do not act capriciously or lawlessly. There are rules involved in the very constitution of the active pro- perties, and these rules are not beyond the possibility of being discovered and expressed. The senses indeed can- not detect them, but they may be found out by internal observation. Nor does it appear that this law can be discovered immediately by consciousness, any more than the law of gravitation can be perceived by the eye. But the operations of the mental properties are under the eye of consciousness just as those of gravitation are under the senses; and by careful observation, analysis, and ge- neralization, we may from the acts reach the laws of the acts. He who has reached the exact expression of our mental properties, is in possession of a law which is native or innate. (3.) As a third position, it is capable of being esta- blished that the mind has original perceptions, which ori- ginal perceptions may be described as intuitive. Every one will acknowledge that the mind has perceptions through the senses, and I shall endeavour to show, as we advance, that it has perceptions of the understanding 20 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. and of the moral faculty: some of these perceptions are, no doubt, secondary and derivative, but the secondary imply primary perceptions, and the derivative original ones. Thus perception of distance by the eye may be deri- vative: but it implies an original perception, by the eye, of a surface. It is by a process of reasoning that I know that the square of the hypothenuse of a right-angled tri- angle is equal to the square of the other two sides: but this reasoning proceeds on certain axiomatic truths whose certainty is seen at once, as that “if equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal.” Let it be observed that we are now in a region in which are loftier properties than those possessed by inert matter; still these higher have rules as well as the lower or material properties. The original perceptions by sense, or reason, or moral power, have all their laws, which it should be the business of psychology or of metaphysics to discover and determine. These original perceptions may be represented as intui- tions inasmuch as they look immediately on the object or truth. The rules or laws which they obey may be de- scribed as intuitive principles ; it is the office of mental science to discover them by a process of introspection, abstraction, and comparison. (4.) It is possible to defend a fourth position, that the mind can discover necessary and universal truth. Not that I propose to substantiate this statement at this stage of our inquiries, still I may announce it, and show how it is not impossible to establish it. The mind declares that these two straight lines before it do not enclose a space. It does more: it declares of every other two straight lines conceived, that they cannot enclose a space. It says of these two straight lines, that if they proceed an inch without being nearer each other, that they will proceed an ell, a mile, or a myriad of miles, without being nearer; nay, it declares of all such parallel POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. 27 lines, that they may be prolonged for ever without meet- ing. These are specimens of a large class of truths, which the mind perceives to be true, and necessarily true. There are logical truths—such as that whatever is predicated of a class may be predicated of all the mem- bers of the class, and moral truths—such as that sin is deserving of reprobation, which are also necessary and universal. But if the mind may—as I maintain that it can and does—rise to the discovery of such truths, it must be by native laws, the expression of which will give us metaphysical science, just as the expression of the laws which material phenomena obey gives us physical science. But it will be said that we discover all this by experi- ence. e are not at this stage of inquiry in circum- stances to have the relation between intuition and expe- rience definitively pointed out. But (5.) It may be stated, as a fifth position, that the very acquisition of experience implies native laws or principles. So far from experience being able to account for innate principles, innate principles are required to account for the treasures of experience. For how is it that man is enabled to gather experience ? How is he different in this respect from the stock or the stone, from the vege- table or the brute, which can acquire no experience, at least no such experience ? Plainly because he is endowed with capacities for this end; and these faculties must have some law or principle on which they proceed. Ex- perience, in the narrow sense, must mean, what we have personally noticed. Even in noticing this, there must be faculties, with principles involved in them, at work. But a personal experience would of itself be valueless to man; it would not and could not enable him to rise from the known to the unknown, to argue from the past to the future. But man can from the known discover the un- known, from the past he can anticipate the future ; and 28 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. when he does so, he must proceed on some principle which is capable of exposition, and ought to be ex- pressed. And if man be capable, as I maintain he is, of reaching necessary and universal truth, he must proceed on principles which can never be derived from experience. Twenty times have we tried, and found that two straight lines do not enclose a space: this does not authorize us to affirm that they never can enclose a space, otherwise we might argue that, because we had seen a judge and his wig twenty times together, they must therefore be together through all eternity. A hundred times have I seen a spark kindle gunpowder : this does not entitle me to declare that it will do so the thousandth or the mil- lionth time, or wherever the spark and the gunpoAvder are found. The gathered knowledge and wisdom of man, and his power of prediction, thus imply more than experience: they presuppose faculties to enable him to gather experience, and in some cases involve necessary principles which enable him, and justify him, as he acts on his ability, to rise from a limited experience to an unlimited and necessary law. But it may be urged that Ave reach these results by reasoning. I reply that (6.) A sixth position may be established, that reasoning proceeds on principles Avhicli cannot be proved by reason- ing, but must be assumed, and assumed as seen intui- tively to be true. In all ratiocination there must be some- thing from which Ave argue. That from which Ave argue is the premiss,—in the Aristotelian analysis of argument, it is the two premisses. But as we go back and back, AAre must at length come to something which cannot be proven. That which cannot be proven must be assumed, but surely not assumed capriciously; if assumed capri- ciously, it can yield no proper foundation, and if not assumed arbitrarily, it must be according to some rule POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. 29 or principle which should be expounded and stated by the metaphysician. How can we reason but from what we know ? and in going back we come to truths which we know directly, that is, by intuition, and the law of this intuition should be evolved. It might further be shown that there must be a mental principle involved— it is the Dictum in the Aristotelian account of reasoning ■—in the process by which we connect the conclusion with the premisses; for were there no such principle, the ratiocination would be arbitrary, and it would be vain for any mail to endeavour to convince his neighbour, or even to try to keep himself consistent. Such considera- tions as these show that at the foundation of argument, and at every stage of the superstructure, there are mental principles involved which are either intuitive or depend on principles which are intuitive. Sect. II. The Native Convictions of the Mind are of the Nature of Perceptions or Intuitions. In some cases there are external objects presented; the mind looks upon them, and the conviction at once springs up. Thus it is that it knows immediately this particular body, this paper or table, as occupying space. In other cases it is something within the mind that is contemplated; it is self in some particular exercise,—say thinking or feeling. In many instances the object pre- sented in the mind is the result of a prior mental process. Thus, having at a former time seen two straight lines, we now, in our thinking moods, image or represent them; and the mind, on the contemplation, proclaims at once that they cannot enclose a space. Or we have occasion to consider some particular voluntary sentiment of a fel- low-man,—say his cherishing malice against another man, and we proclaim it to be evil, condemnable. In this last instance the act contemplated is not, properly speaking, 30 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. under our immediate view, for it is in the breast of a neighbour, but it is represented to us in our minds, and looking on this representation the mind pronounces a decision. In every case these convictions seem to be of the nature of perceptions, that is, something is presented to us, and the cognition, belief, or judgment is formed. It is on this account that I have, in the title of this Trea- tise, chosen to call them Intuitions. As we advance, we shall find other distinctive characters, the expression of which yields other epithets; but the term Intuitions, that is, perceptions formed by looking in upon objects, seems to bring out the original quality of the native convictions of the mind. Sect. III. Intuitive Convictions rise on the Contem- plation of Objects Presented or Represented to the mind. Metaphysicians have often given such an account of them as to leave the impression that the mind creates them independent of objects, or that, at the utmost, expe- rience furnishes merely the occasion, on the occurrence of which the mind fashions them by its own inherent power. I shall have occasion to show that the relation between the intuitive powers and objects is of a much closer and more dependent character than this account would lead us to suppose. In intuition we look into the object, we discover something in it, or belonging to it, or we discover a relation between it and some other ob- ject. Were the object taken away, the perception would be meaningless, indeed it would altogether cease. In- tuition is a perception of an object, and of something in it or pertaining to it. Perception, without something looked into, would be as contradictory as vision without an object seen, or touch without an object felt. In our cognitions we know objects, or qualities of objects, we POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. 31 know self as thinking, or body as extended. In belief we entertain a trust regarding certain objects that they are so and so,—of time, for example, that it can come to no end. In judgment we discover certain relations be- tween two or more objects, as that a mode implies a substance. Our intuitive convictions are thus not ideas, notions, judgments, formed apart from objects, but are in fact discoveries of something in objects, or relating to them.* Sect. IY. The Intuitions of the Mind are primarily DIRECTED TO INDIVIDUAL OBJECTS. I shall have occasion to show, when I come to distin- guish and classify the intuitions, that some are of the nature of cognitions and beliefs, while others are of the nature of judgments. But whatever be their distinctive nature, they always, as intuitions, primarily contemplate objects as individuals. If I know, or believe in anything, it is an existing thing, that is, as singular. If I form an intuitive judgment, that is, make a comparison, it is still in regard to two or more objects considered as singulars; and so far as we pass beyond this, there is always, as I shall endeavour to show, a discursive process involved. A very different account is often given, if not formally, at least implicitly, of intuition or of intuitive reason. Man is represented as gazing immediately on the true, the beautiful, the good, meaning in the abstract, or in the general. It is admitted that there must be some sort of experience, some individual object presented as the occa- sion, but the mind, being thus roused into activity, is re- presented as contemplating, by direct vision, such things as space and time, substance and quality, cause and effect, the infinite, and moral good. I hope to be able to * Locke laid strong hold of the features specified in this Section and the last; see infra, Part I. Book II. Chap. III. 32 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. show that this theory is altogether mistaken. Our ap- peal on this subject must be to the consciousness and the memory, and these give a very different account of the process which passes through the mind when it is employed about such objects. Intuitively the mind con- templates a particular body as occupying space and be- ing in space, and it is by a subsequent intellectual pro- cess, in which abstraction acts an important part, that the idea of space is formed. Intuitively the mind con- templates an event as happening in time, and then by a further process arrives at the notion of time. The mind has not intuitively an idea of cause or causation in the abstract, but discovering a given effect, it looks for a spe- cific cause. It does not form some sort of vague notion of a general infinite, but fixing its attention on some in- dividual thing,—such as space, or time, or God,—it is constrained to believe it to be infinite. The child has not formed to itself a refined idea of moral good, but contemplating a given action it proclaims it to be good or evil. The same remark holds good of the intuitive judgments of the mind, that is, when it compares two or more things, and proclaims them at once to agree or dis- agree. I do not, without a process of discursive thought, pronounce, or even understand, the general maxim that things which are equal to the same things are equal to one another, but on discovering that first one bush and then another bush are of the same height as my staff, I decide that the two bushes are equal to one another. It will be shown in next Section that the mind has the power of generalizing the individual cognitions or judg- ments of the intuitions, and in doing so it may arrive at most important truth. It will come out, too, that intui- tion may fasten on the general proposition and pronounce decisions in which it is involved. But in the formation of the general maxim, there is a process of logical thought POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. 33 involved for which the intuition is not responsible. It is only in the form of convictions regarding individuals presenting themselves that our intuitions manifest them- selves in all men—in children and savages for instance. The boy decides that the ball which he holds in his hand cannot be at the same time in the hand of some other boy who may pretend to have it; but he has not meanwhile consciously before him the formula that it is impossible for the same body to be in two places at the same time. The individual conviction is in all men when the objects are pressed on their attention, the general maxim is the result of thought and especially of abstraction and ge- neralization. By drawing this distinction we are able to maintain that these .intuitions are native and in all minds, and yet save ourselves from the absurdity in which so many metaphysicians land themselves when they speak of children or infants as employed in contem- plating the ego and the non-ego, personality, externality, subject, and object. The particular conviction is formed by all in a concrete form when the appropriate objects present themselves; but the abstract formula is fashioned by those addicted to reflection, and is not even under- stood except by those whose minds are matured and cul- tivated. Sect. V. The Individual Intuitive Convictions can be Generalized into Maxims, and these are entitled to BE REPRESENTED AS PHILOSOPHIC PRINCIPLES. The native principles in the soul are analogous to the physical laws operating in external nature. Both one and other act at all times, on the necessary conditions being supplied. Like the physiological processes of re- spiration and the circulation of the blood, the intuitions do not depend for their operation on any voluntary de- termination of the human mind, and they act whether 34 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. we observe them or no; indeed they often act best when we are taking no notice of them. We cannot command their exercise on the one hand, nor prohibit it on the other. A greater or less number of them are working in the soul at every waking moment of our existence. It is always to be remembered indeed that they are mental and not material laws; but, making allowance for this, they may be regarded as operating very much like the great physical or physiological laws of chemical affinity, or of nervous irritability, or of the reflex nervous system. As they act in an analogous manner, so they may be discovered in much the same way as the laws of the material universe, that is, by the method of induc- tion. The laws of matter are discovered by the observation and generalization of their individual operations. With the exception of a few metaphysicians of the schools of Schelling or Hegel, no one now maintains that these laws can be discovered by a priori speculation. Nor can they be detected by mere sense,—by eye, or touch, or ear; no man ever yet saw, or touched, or heard, a law of nature. All that falls under the perception of the senses are individual facts, and those generally concrete or com- plex ; that is, the object is presented as exhibiting more than one quality at the same time, or the effect is the result of a variety of causes. In order to reach the law by an observation of the facts, there is need first of all of a judicious analysis, or, as Bacon calls it, the necessary “ rejections and exclusions,” or the separation and set- ting aside of the extraneous matter of the mixed pheno- menon ; that is, the matter which does not belong to the law or agent we are seeking to discover. Having made these appropriate rejections, we now generalize the facts—that is, find out where they agree—and thus arrive at the discovery of the physical law. POSITIVE PROPOSITIONS. 35 It is in much the same way, mutatis mutandis, that we discover the laws of our original and native convic- tions. I boldly affirm that it is as impossible to deter- mine them as it is to settle the laws of the external uni- verse by a priori cogitation or logical division and dis- section. As they cannot be elaborated by speculation on the one hand, so neither do they fall under the immediate cognizance of consciousness on the other. All that comes under the consciousness is individual: it is an object now present; it is the mind in some state or mode. But our modifications of mind at any given moment are always more or less complex; that is, there is more than one property in exercise, though of course combined in the unity of the mind. But, by a sharp analysis, it is always possible to separate the different elements, and fix the attention exclusively on that which alone pertains to the law or property we are seeking to evolve. Exami- ning carefully the nature of the acts which seem to flow from the same principle, we generalize them; and, if we do so accurately, we obtain the exact nature of the prin- ciple, and can embody it in a verbal expression. The principle thus discovered and enunciated is pro- perly a metaphysical one; it is a truth above sense, a truth of mind, a truth of reason. It is different in its origin and authority from the general rules reached by experience, such as the law of gravitation, or the law of chemical affinity, or the law of the distribution of animals over the earth’s surface. These latter are the mere ge- neralizations of an experience necessarily limited; they hold good merely in the measure of our experience, and as experience can never reach all possible cases, so the rule can never be absolute ; we can never say that there may not be exceptions. Laws of the former kind are of a higher or deeper nature, they are the generalization of convictions carrying necessity with them, and a consequent 36 GENERAL PROPOSITIONS. universality in their very nature. They are entitled to be regarded as in an especial sense philosophic princi- ples, being the ground to which we come when we follow any system of truth sufficiently far down, and competent to act as a basis on which to erect a superstructure of science. They are truths of our original constitution, having the sanction of Him who hath given us our con- stitution, and graven them there with His own finger. It is ever to be borne in mind, however, that the de- tection and exact expression of these intuitive principles is always a delicate and is often a most difficult opera- tion. Did they fall immediately under the eye of con- sciousness, the work would be a comparatively easy one; we should only have to look within in order to see them. But all that consciousness can notice are their indivi- dual exercises mixed up one with another and with all other actings of the mind. It requires a microscopic eye, and much analytic skill, to detect the various fibres in the complex structure, and to follow each through its various windings and entanglements to its source. 37 BOOK II. CHARACTER OE INTUITIONS, AND METHOD OE EMPLOYING THEM. CHAPTER I. MAKES AND PECULIARITIES OF INTUITION. Sect. I. Tests. But how are we to distinguish a primitive conviction which does not need probation, and which we may not even doubt, from propositions which we are not required to believe till evidence is produced ? Are we entitled to appeal, when we please and as we please, to supposed first truths? Have we the privilege, when we wish to adhere to a favourite opinion, to declare that we see it to be true intuitively, and thus at once get rid of all objections, and of the necessity for even instituting an examination ? May we, when hard pressed, or defeated in argument, resort, as it suits us, to an original prin- ciple which we assume without evidence, and declare to be beyond the reach of refutation? It is one of the aims of this treatise to limit the confidence we put in our supposed intuitions, and lay a stringent restraint on the appeal to truths which are represented as above probation. There can be tests propounded sufficient to determine with precision what convictions are, and what 38 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. convictions are not, entitled to be regarded as intuitive, and these tests are such that they admit of an easy application, requiring only a moderate degree of careful consideration of the maxim proffered as claiming our assent. 1. The primary mark of intuitive truth is self-evidence. It must be evident, and it must have its evidence in the object. The mind, on the bare contemplation of the ob- ject, must see it to be so and so, must see it to be so at once, without requiring any foreign evidence or mediate proof. That the planet Mars is inhabited, or that it is not inhabited, is not a first truth, for it is not evident on the bare contemplation of the object. That the isle of Madagascar is inhabited, even this is not a primary con- viction ; we believe it because of secondary testimony. Nay, that the three angles of a triangle are together equal to two right-angles, is not a primitive judgment, for it needs other truths coming between to carry our conviction. But that there is an extended object before me when I look at a table or a wall, that I who look at these objects exist, and that two marbles added to two marbles here will be equal to two marbles added to two marbles there,—these are truths that are evident on the bare contemplation of the objects, and need no foreign facts, or considerations derived from any other quarter, to establish them. But it may be asked, can we certainly know what truths are self-evident? Are we not liable to be de- ceived, especially by education and prepossessions ? Have not some declared propositions to be self-evident, which have afterwards been positively disproved ? The reply is, that if we devote our minds earnestly to the object, we cannot readily go astray. No doubt, it is possible to fall into error in the application of this test, as in the application of any other; but this can take place only MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 39 by negligence, by refusing to go round the object to which the conviction refers, and to look upon it as it is in itself, and in all its aspects. In specifying this test as the fundamental one, I do not mean that it can be applied without much and careful inspection. It is for- tunate that we have a secondary test to determine the presence of the primary characteristic. 2. Necessity is a secondary mark of intuitive truth. I am not inclined to fix on this as the original or essen- tial characteristic. I shrink from maintaining that a pro- position is true because we must believe it. A propo- sition is true as being true, and certain propositions are seen by us to be self-evidently true. I would not ground the evidence on the necessity of belief, but I would as- cribe the irresistible nature of the conviction to the self- evidence. As the necessity flows from the self-evidence, so it may become a test of it, and a test not difficult of application. When an object or truth is self-evident, necessity always attaches to our convictions regarding it. And according to the nature of the conviction, so is the ne- cessity attached. We shall see that some of the convic- tions are of the nature of knowledge, others of the na- ture of belief, a third class of the nature of judgments, in which we compare objects known or believed in. In the first our cognition is necessary, in the second our belief is necessary, in the third our judgment is neces- sary. I know self as an existing thing: this is a neces- sary cognition; I must entertain it, and never can be driven from it. That space exceeds my wfidest imagina- tion of space: this is a necessary belief, I must believe it. That every effect has a cause : this is a necessary judg- ment ; I must decide in this way. Wherever there is such a conviction, it is a sign of an intuitive perception. Necessity too may be employed in a negative form, and 40 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. this is often the most decisive form. If I know imme- diately that there is an extended object before me in the book which I read, I cannot be made to know that there is not an extended object before me. If I must believe that time had no beginning, I cannot be made to believe that it has had a beginning. Necessitated as I am to decide that two parallel lines cannot meet, I cannot be made to decide that they can meet. Necessity as a test may thus assume two forms, and we may take the one best suited to our purpose at the time. In the use of a very little care and discernment, this test will settle for us as to any given truth, whether it is or is not self- evident. 3. Catholicity may be employed as a tertiary test. By catholicity is meant that the conviction is entertained by all men, or at least by all men possessed of intelli- gence, when the objects are presented. I am not in- clined to use this as a primary test. For in the first place it is not easy to ascertain, or at least to settle abso- lutely, what truths may claim this common consent of humanity; and even though this were determined, still it might be urged in the second place that this does not prove that it is necessary or original, but simply that it is a native property,—like the appetite for food among all men,—and would still leave it possible for opponents to maintain that there may be intelligent beings in other worlds who accord no such assent, just as we can conceive beings in the other parts of the universe who have no craving for meat or drink. But while not inclined to use catholicity as a primary test, I think it may come in at times as an auxiliary one. For what is in all men, may most probably come from what is not only native, but necessary; and must also in all probability be self- evident, or at least follow very directly from what is self- evident. Catholicity, when conjoined with necessity, may MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 41 determine very readily and precisely whether a conviction is intuitive. Important purposes are served by the combination of these two tests: that is, necessity and catholicity. By the first we have a personal assurance which can never be shaken, and of which no one can deprive us. Though the whole world were to declare that we do not exist, or that a cruel action is good, we would not give up our own personal conviction in favour of their declara- tion. By the other principle we have confidence in addressing our fellow-men, for we know that there are grounds of thought common to them and to us, and to these we can appeal in reasoning with them. By the one I am enabled, yea, compelled, to hold by my per- sonality, and maintain my independence; by the other I am made to feel that I am one of a large family, every member of which has the same principles of belief as I myself have. The one gives me the argument from pri- vate judgment, the other the argument from common or catholic consent. The concurrence of the two should suffice to protect me from scepticism of every kind, whe- ther it relate to the world within or the world without, whether to physical or moral truths. These marks are as clear and as easily applied, and are quite as decisive for testing reason in its primary or intuitive exercise, as the syllogism is in testing reason in its secondary or derivative operation; that is, as infer- ence or reasoning. Sect. II. Different Aspects of Intuitions, and their Theoretical Characters. Hitherto we have been approaching onr subject by a somewhat winding path, catching glimpses of the posi- tion of the building, and of some of its principal turrets. We may now walk up directly to it, and take a survey 42 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. of its general form, and ascertain the mode of entering it, with the view of afterwards exploring its apartments one by one. It will be found to present three sides, sides of one fabric, but each with its peculiarities. The intuitions may be considered first as laws, rules, principles regulating the original action and the primi- tive perceptions of the mind. Or secondly, they may be regarded as individual perceptions, or convictions mani- festing themselves in consciousness. Or thirdly, they may be contemplated as abstract notions, or general rules elaborated out of the individual exercises. We cannot have a distinct or adequate view of our intuitions un- less we carefully distinguish these the one from the other. The whole of the confusion, and the greater part of the errors, which have appeared in the discussions about innate ideas and a priori principles, have sprung from neglecting these distinctions, or from not carrying them out consistently. In each of these sides the in- tuitions present distinct characters, and many affirma- tions may be properly made of the original principles of the mind under one of these aspects, which would by no means hold good of the others. I. They may be contemplated as Laws, Rules, or Principles Guiding the Mind. Hence they have been called KOLvdl iTpoXrjfieLs, /coival evvoicu, irpwrai evvoicu, forms and regulative principles. Under this aspect (1.) They are native. Hence they have been called na- tural, innate, connate, implanted, constitutional. All these phrases point to the circumstance that they are not ac- quired by practice, nor the result of experience, but are in the mind naturally, as constituents of its very being, and involved in its higher exercises. In this respect they are analogous to universal gravitation and chemi- cal affinity, which are not produced in bodies as they operate, but are in the very nature of bodies, and the MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 43 springs of their action. It is thus—that is, by an original property of his being—that man is led to look on body as occupying space, on any given effect as having a cause, and on certain actions as being morally good or evil. (2.) They are reyultaive* They rule the mind in its original and primitive energies, both of thought and be- lief. They lead the mind, for example, on discovering a quality, to connect it with substance; on contemplating time, to declare that it cannot have had a beginning; and on having a vicious action brought before it, to decide that it is deserving of punishment. This characteristic is brought before us by the phrases so often applied to them,—forms, laws, rules, canons, and principles. They lead and guide the deeper mental action, just as the chemical and vital properties conduct and control the composition of bodies and the organization of plants. It is to be carefully noticed that, as regulative principles, they are not dependent, in themselves or in their ac- tion, on our observation of them; indeed they must be guiding the mind before we can observe them ; still less are they dependent on the will of the possessor, which has merely an indirect control over them, and this only by bringing before the cognitive or representative powers of the mind the objects which evoke them. (3.) They are catholic, or common. That is, they are * The phrase Regulative has been used by Kant in Kr. d. r. Ver. transcen. Doc. der Urtheilskraft, ch. iii., where he speaks of certain principles as being constitutive and others regulative. The distinction proceeds on certain Kantian views, and cannot be admitted by any natural realist. Sir W. Hamilton has adopted the phrase Regulative (‘ Metaphysics,’ Lect. 38), and agrees so far with Kant that he reckons many of the regulative principles of the mind, such as those about space and time and cause, as guaranteeing no objective reality. The phrase is a good one, but in adopting it, care must be taken to dissociate it from all the peculiarities of the Kantian and Hamiltonian philosophy. The regulative..principles guide the mind so as that it discovers what is in things, whereas, according to Kant, they guarantee nothing as to things. 44 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. in every human mind. Not that they are in all men as formalized principles; under this aspect, as we shall see forthwith, they come before the minds of comparatively few. Some of them are perhaps not even manifested in all minds; certainly some of them are not manifested, in their higher forms, in the souls of all. In infants some of them have not yet made their appearance, and among persons low in the scale of intelligence, they do not come out in their loftier exercises; just as the plant does not come all at once into full flower,—just as the plant, in unfavourable circumstances, may never come into seed at all. Still the capacity is there, needing only favourable circumstances—that is, the appropriate objects pressed on the attention—to foster it into developed forms. Under this aspect, the epithets common, catholic, have been ap- plied to them; they have been represented as the univer- sal attributes of humanity, and as belonging to man as man. But it is to be specially noticed that in this whole ge- neral view of them, they are not before consciousness as principles. They do indeed come out into conscious- ness, not however as laws, but as individual convictions. This negative characteristic has been often referred to when they have been spoken of as latent, occult, hiding themselves, as roots covered up in the substance of the soul, as foundations beneath the ground, as faculties re- quiring to be developed, and as evoked into exercise only on the occasion of experience. II. They may be contemplated as Convictions Mani- fested in Consciousness. Hence they are called espe- cially intuitions, spontaneous or natural convictions, in- nate ideas, and primitive beliefs and judgments. It is only under this aspect that we can directly apply to them the tests of intuition specified in last Section. Under what restriction they apply to our intuitions as regulative MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 45 or as generalized principles may be afterwards pointed out. We have already in our survey gathered what are some of the characteristics of these our conscious convic- tions ; still, what we before enounced will require to be formally stated in its proper place alongside of some other theoretical characteristics, to be now unfolded. (1.) They are perceptions. This feature was caught and has been expressed by those who speak of them as percep- tions, apperceptions, senses, apprehensions, and who re- present them as seeing, looking, regarding, contemplating. (2.) They look at objects. Hence they have been re- presented as comprising knowledge, cognition, and dis- cernment. It is of the greater moment to bring out this characteristic, from the circumstance that they have often been too much dissociated from objects. In read- ing some of the exaggerated accounts of them, the im- pression is apt to be left that they are formed by the native power of the mind, independent of objects altoge- ther ; and even in more guarded statements, the presen- tation of objects is spoken of as merely the occasion on which they spring up.* In opposition to all this, I maintain that they are perceptions of objects, of objects themselves or something in objects. Sometimes the ob- jects are external to the mind, as when I intuitively look on body as extended or on space as having no limits. In other cases the objects are within the mind, as when I look on self, and discover that it has being and per- sonality, or on a certain representation in the mind, say of a benevolent action, which I discern to be good. Or the intuition may manifest itself in the form of judgments or comparisons; but even in such, it is a perception of objects as having points of relation. It is the very nature of the regulative principles of the mind that they * This view is examined infra, Part III. Book I. Chap. II. sect, v., Supplementary. 46 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. lead us to look at objects, and to discover what is in them. (3.) They look at objects as singulars. In this re- spect they are analogous to the senses and consciousness, and have often been characterized as senses and as con- sciousnesses. This peculiarity has already been explained in a general way. (4.) They are immediate. That is, our minds, in in- tuition, gaze directly on the object. Hence they have been called feelings,—language which may be allowed if meant merely to express that they are analogous to feel- ing or touch as it feels or handles an object, but which is of a most misleading character if intended to signify that they are of the nature of emotions. Under this aspect they have been called visions, inspirations, revela- tions. Hence too the special name Intuitions applied to them, to denote that they see the object as it were face to face, and with nothing coming between to aid the view on the one hand, or obstruct it on the other. This character it is which affords what I have described as the primary test, that is, self-evidence. In the case of many objects, we cannot look on them directly. Thus we who live in the nineteenth century cannot be spectators of the events which happened in the first century. When dwelling in these islands, we cannot gaze on the Himalayas or Andes; we can contemplate such objects only indirectly, and through something else as a medium. But in every intuition we look at once on the corresponding object: it is thus we are conscious immediately of self in action; thus that we gaze on body as occupying space ; thus that we regard space as un- bounded; thus that we regard a certain disposition as good or as evil. But to prevent misapprehension it is necessary here to offer an explanation. When I say that the object ]\IARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 47 is present, I do not mean by this that the object must be a bodily one, or one external to the mind. The ob- ject may quite as frequently be a mental as a material one. The object may even be represented, in a loose and inaccurate sense, as an absent one. Thus I may pro- nounce of an event which happened far away, in India, that it must have had a cause, and of a deed of self-sacri- fice, done a thousand years ago, that it must have been good. But then it is not, properly speaking, to the dis- tant event that the intuition looks, but to the representa- tion of it in the mind. It is only mediately, through the representation, that the intuition can refer to the actual occurrence, and this on the supposition that the repre- sentation is correct; and if the representation be errone- ous, or even mutilated, or imperfect, it cannot be legi- timately applied to the event. Correctly speaking, the object is always present when the intuition gazes on it; it is either a bodily object immediately before the mind, or it is a presentation or representation within the mind itself. (5.) There is a conviction of necessity attached to every one of them. Hence they have been described as irresis- tible, unavoidable, compelling belief, and not admitting of doubt or dispute. We have already had this character under our notice, and it may yet come before us in its applications, and in regard to the supposed diversity in the necessity as attached to different convictions, and it is not needful to enter more minutely into its nature in this general survey. It should be carefully noticed that the necessity attaches itself directly only to our in- dividual perceptions. The general formula carries with it no such conviction till it is shown that it has been correctly formed. There may be legitimate doubts and disputes as to many proposed philosophic maxims, as to whether they are or are not correct. Still, as will be 48 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. shown, the necessity being in the singulars, goes up into the universals on the condition of the universal being pro- perly formed. (6.) They are original and independent. Hence they have been called first, primary, or primitive truths, and been described as origins, dp%al, or original principles, seeds, roots, and starting-points, and characterized as un- derived, independent, self-sufficient. The mind sponta- neously starts with such, it sets out from them, and in doing so, feels that it has need of no probation or foreign support of any kind. A large body of our convictions, even of the surest, are derived; they are dependent on something else. Thus we are dependent for our historical information on the testimony of our fellow-men; for our belief in the great mysteries opened in the Bible, on the testimony of God; for our conviction of the propositions in the Sixth Book of Euclid, on the prefixed axioms, and on the propositions in the other five books, and generally for the last conclu- sion of a chain of reasoning, on all the links which have preceded. But in intuition, or, as it may be called, intui- tive reason, our conviction hangs on nothing else. That the whole, orange or earth, is equal to the sum of its several parts, is a truth which depends on no other. There may be many asseverations to which we do not give our assent till evidence of some kind is furnished. There may be true propositions from which we withhold our concurrence till they are proven. Very possibly there may be inhabitants on that other side of the moon which no human eye has seen, but I wait for evidence before I give a decision one way or another. It seems very certain that there have been volcanoes in the moon, but men did not give their credence till traces of eruptive formations were discovered by the telescope. But there are propositions which do not require proof, even as they MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 49 do not admit of proof, and yet our conviction of them, to say the least of it, is as strong as of the truths most firmly established by probation. There are some ap- prehensions, some propositions, in regard to which the mind sees that it needs mediate proof in order to con- vince it that they imply a reality or a truth; but there are others, in regard to which it sees that they have in themselves all that is needful to gain our assent. There are some truths for which reason demands support before it will give its adhesion to them; there are others, in regard to which reason says, that they do not require to be borne up by any external evidence. It is not because of any defect in the veracity of intuitive truths, that they do not admit of probation ; it is rather because of the fullness and strength of their veracity. It is, in a sense, owing to a deficiency in certain truths, or rather, a deficiency in our minds with respect to them, that they require something to lean on. Thus it is because of some defect or perplexity in the truth (to us), that mathemati- cians cannot solve, except approximately, the problem of three bodies attracting each other. It is because of the self-sufficiency of certain truths, such as that the think- ing me exists, and that extended bodies exist, and that gratitude is a virtue, it is because our minds are so con- stituted as to see them at once, that they require no proof; we need no other light in which to see them, they shine in their own light. But let us properly understand and limit this account given of them; when they are said to be independent, it does not mean that they are independent of objects: we have before seen that our intuitions are perceptions of or regarding objects. (6.) Some of them are catholic,—that is, in all men. Hence they have been described as common ideas and notions. We have seen that as regulative powers they 50 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. are in all men, without exception. But all of them do not, therefore, come forth in actual energies; many of them in their developed and manifested form are the re- sult of growth, and some of them seem to lie dormant in many minds from the want of proper fostering circum- stances. Still, there are some of them, such as the intui- tion of self and the intuition of body in space, which are formed by all men in their individual and concrete form. III. They may be contemplated as Notions or Prin- ciples FORMED BY ABSTRACTION AND GENERALIZATION. Under this aspect they are irpwra naturae judicia, a 'priori notions, definitions, maxims, and axioms. Thus considered they cannot be represented as com- mon or universal in the sense of being in all men. If we look to the hundreds of millions of human beings on the face of the earth, including infants, children, savages and the unreflecting masses, there is but a very small minority of the family of man who have ever had such notions or maxims before them. Every human being, if he sees an object before him, will refuse to give his as- sent to the assertion that this object does not exist; but how few beyond the limited circle of professed metaphy- sicians have ever had consciously before them the princi- ple that it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time. Millions of men, women, and children are every hour acting on the intuition of causation—are taking food, for example, in the belief that it will nourish them, though they never have had the principle consciously before them, and know not so much as that there is a principle of causation. But under this view, (1.) The General Maxim is Necessary, on the condition of the generalization out of the individual convictions being properly formed. It is to be constantly kept in mind, that MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 51 the necessity attaches in the first instance to the singular conviction looking to its objects. But the necessity being in the individuals, may be made to go up into the general, provided the general has been legitimately drawn from the individuals. With this proviso, a very important one however, the maxim is not only true, it is necessarily true, it cannot be otherwise. If any one were to lay down the principle that “ everything must have a cause,” he would not be announcing a necessary truth; for while there is a necessary conviction in every exercise of mind regarding causation, he has not seized it properly, nor expressed it correctly. But if the maxim that “ every- thing which begins to be must have a cause” be, as I maintain it is, the proper generalization of the peculiarity of the individual conviction, it may be regarded as a ne- cessary one. In this respect it differs from the general laws of nature reached by observation; as for example, that hydrogen chemically combines with oxygen in the proportion of one to eight. We cannot, from the bare contemplation of hydrogen and oxygen, say that they must unite in any particular proportion, or that they shall unite at all. The law is reached by the pure obser- vation of particular cases, and these, however many, are still limited in number; for all the particular cases, that is, of the mutual action of hydrogen and oxygen in the universe, never can fall under our notice. The law may, after all, be a mere modification of a higher and wider law; there may be exceptions to it in other worlds ; it is in no sense absolutely or universally certain. But on the bare contemplation of two given straight lines, I perceive, without any succession of trials, that they cannot enclose a space. I perceive that this would be true of any other two straight lines that could fall under my notice, and thus I reach the general maxim that no two straight lines can enclose a space, a maxim admitting of excep- 52 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. tions at no time and at no place. In regard to the one class of general truths, I have formed a law from a neces- sarily limited, out of an indefinite number of cases. In regard to the other, our generalizations are of convictions in our own mind, each of which carries necessity in it. In order to the formation of the latter, we have not to go out in search of external instances in the mental or material world, nor to number and to weigh such; we have all the elements in each of our convictions; and if we generalize properly, by what in some cases is an easy, but in others a somewhat difficult process, we reach general truths, which have the same necessity as the individual convic- tions. (2.) They are Universal, Immutable, Eternal: only however on the same condition as they are necessary, that is, on the understanding that the general maxim is duly fashioned out of the individual convictions. But here it will be necessary to distinguish between two applications of the word ‘universal’ which have often been confounded. Sometimes a principle is called universal because it is in all men or avowed by all men. I have in this treatise adopted the word ‘catholic,’ or ‘common,’ to express this property of intuition. But when we say a truth is universal, we may mean that it is universally true, that is, admits of no exceptions, and it is in this latter appli- cation I use the word ‘ universal.’ Universality in this sense follows from necessity; the maxim which is ne- cessarily, must be universally, true.* It is only in this * That a truth is accepted by common or catholic consent, and that it is without exception, are not the same, though they have often been confounded under the one epithet ‘universal.’ Sir W. Hamilton says (Note A. p. 754, Reid’s Works), “Necessity and universality may be re- garded as coincident; for when a belief is necessary, it is, eo ipso, univer- sal ; and that a belief is universal is a certain index that it must be ne- cessary (see Leibnitz, ‘Nouveaux Essais,’ lib. i. s. 4).” Hamilton means by universality, universality of belief; which also Leibnitz means in the passage referred to—the language he uses is, “ consentement universel.” MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 53 meaning that the term can be applied to the maxims which express in a general form the law of our intuitive convictions. Such maxims admit of exceptions at no time and in no place. They are true in our own land, but they are true also in other lands; true in our world, they are true in all other worlds; true in all ages of time, they are equally true through all eternity. Hence they have been called expressively unchangeable, imperishable, and eternal truths. (3.) They are fundamental. Hence they have been described as radical, as grounds or foundations, and called fundamental laws of thought and belief. They are the truths we come to, when we analyze a discussion into its elements. We may even set out with them in ar- gument or in speculation, provided we have adequately generalized them. All demonstrated and derived truths will be found, if we pursue them sufficiently far down, to be resting on such fundamental truths. In controver- sies on profound topics, especially in theology and meta- physics, those who engage in them feel themselves ever coming down to a ground beneath which they cannot get. In searching into the structure of argument, we find, But it is surely conceivable (I do not say, actual), that a conviction might be necessary to one man and not to all men; and there are in fact beliefs in man, which are universal, such as that the sun will rise tomorrow, which are not necessary. Kant used ‘universal’ in the sense of ‘true without exception,’ and very properly remarks, that the necessity and universality belong inseparably to each other, but that sometimes the one and some- times the other test admits of the easier or more effective application. “ Nothwendigkeit und strenge Allgemeinheit sind also sichere Kenn- zeichen einer Erkenntniss a priori, und gehoren auch unzertrennlich zu einander. "Weil es aber im Gebrauche derselben bisweilen leichter ist, die empirische Beschranktheit derselben, als die Zufalligkeit in den Ur- theilen, oder es auch mannigmal einleuchtender ist, die unbeschrankte Allgemeinheit, die wir einem TJrtheile beilegen, als die Noth wendigkeit desselben zu zeigen, so ist rathsam, sich gedachter beider Kriterien, deren jedes fur sich unfelilbar ist, abgesondert zu bedienen” (K. d. r. V., Einleit. Auf. 2. Werke, bd. ii. p. 697: Eosenkranz). 54 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. as we follow it from conclusion to premiss, hanging on a premiss which is self-supporting. The sceptic is ever compelling the philosopher to go down to these depths. The dogmatist, in building his structure, is entitled to start with them as assumptions,—he must be the more careful that what he builds on be really the rock. On them other truths may rest, but they themselves rest on none. There may ever be an appeal to them, but there can never be an appeal from them. Now in order to avoid confusion, and the error which springs from confusion, it is essential that we go round these three sides of this shield of truth, that we read what is on each, and carefully distinguish the inscriptions. If any one having occasion to employ intuition neglect to do this, he will ever be liable to affirm of the intuition under one aspect, what is true of it only in another, or to turn the wrong side towards the weapons of the as- sailant while he keeps the wrong side towards himself. When we are required to speak of them distinctively, our intuitions under the first aspect may be called native laws or regulative principles; under the second aspect, native, spontaneous, or necessary convictions; under the third aspect, universal truths or formalized maxims. As Innate or Regulative Principles they are in all men at all ages; but it is wrong to represent them as being before the consciousness, as being immediately under our notice, as capable of being discovered without abstrac- tion or generalization, or observation, or trouble of any kind. It is wrong to represent them as ideas in the Lockian sense of the term, that is, as apprehensions be- fore consciousness. As Spontaneous Convictions they are immediately under the eye of consciousness, but there they are not in the form of philosophic principles, nor can we say of MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 55 every one of them they appear in all men, and from their earliest infancy. As Universal Truths or General Maxims they are in an especial sense philosophic principles, but then as such they are known only to comparatively few; they can be appealed to in argument only on the condition that their law has been gathered by induction, and carefully ex- pressed, and while there can be no dispute as to the spontaneous convictions, there may be disputes as to whether they have been properly generalized.* At the same time these are after all only the di- verse aspects of one great general fact, and they have relations all to each, and each to all. There is first a mind with its native capacities, each with its rule of ac- tion. In due time these come out into action, .some of them at an earlier, and some of them at a later date, on the appropriate objects being presented, and the actions are before consciousness. As being before consciousness we can observe them by reflection, and discover the na- ture of the law which has all along been in the mind, and in its very constitution. Sect. III. Certain Misapprehensions in regard to the Character op Intuitive Convictions. Looking on the above as the properties and marks of the intuitive convictions of the mind, we see that a wrong account is often given of them. 1. It is wrong to represent them as unaccountable feelings, as blind instincts, as unreasonable impulses. They have nothing whatever of the nature of those feel- ings or emotions which raise up excitement within us, and attach us to certain objects, and draw us away from * In writing this Section, I have kept before me throughout Hamil- ton’s famous Note A, and have freely borrowed from it. But Hamilton has not distinguished between these Three Aspects of Common Sense. 56 CHARACTER OE INTUITIONS. others. Nor should they be put under the same head as the instincts which prompt us to crave for food when we are hungry, or which lead the dog to follow his mas- ter. In such cases the parties obey an impulse, which is not accompanied with knowledge or judgment of any kind, whereas in the perceptions of intuition there is always knowledge involved, and this the most certain of all, immediate knowledge, and in many of them there is judgment looking directly on the objects compared. So far from being unreasonable, they involve a primary exercise of reason superior to all secondary or derivative processes, which ever depend on the primary, and are often inferior in certainty, and can, in no circumstances, rise higher than the fountain from which they have flowed. 2. It is wrong to represent man, so far as he yields to these convictions, as being under some sort of stern and relentless fatality which compels him to go, without yielding him light of any kind. No doubt they con- strain him to acknowledge the existence of certain ob- jects, and the certainty of special truths; but this, not by denying him light, but by affording him the fullest conceivable light, such light that he cannot possibly mistake the object or wander from the path. No doubt he cannot have mediate proof, but it is because he has what the faculties which judge of proof declare to be vastly higher, immediate evidence, or self-evidence. We need no secondary proof, for we have primary, to con- vince us that two parallel lines can never meet. Our intuitions do not compel us against the reason, but they convince us in the highest exercise of reason, and they lead us not against, but by the assent of our clearest and profoundest intelligence. No man is ever, even in his most wayward moods, spontaneously tempted to complain because bound to yield to these convictions. MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 57 When he reflects on their nature, he should rejoice be- cause such is his constitution that he is led to follow and obey them. 3. It is wrong to represent these self-evident truths as being truths merely to the individual, or truths merely to man, or beings constituted like man. There are some who speak and write as if what is truth to one man might not be truth to another man ; as if what is truth to mankind might not be truth to other intelligent beings.* This account might be correct if the convic- tions were borne in upon the mind by a blind natural impulse. But what we perceive by an original intuition * It is not easy to determine tlie precise philosophy of the Sophists, if indeed they had a philosophy. The doctrine of Heraclitus was that all is and is not; that while it does come into being, it forthwith ceases to be. Protagoras, proceeding on this doctrine, declared, r]ai yap irov iravrav xprjpdrav perpov avdpanov eivai, rav pev ovrav, as earl, rav 8e prj ovrav, as ovk eanv. This Socrates expounds as meaning ola pev enaara epol (paiverai, roiavra pev ecrriv epol, oia 8e cro'i (Plato, Thesetetus, 24: Bekker). Aristotle represents Protagoras as maintaining that ra So- tcovvra TravTa ecrriv aKrjdrj /cat ra cftaivipeva (TVTetapli. lib. iii. c. 5: Bonitz), Again, lib. X. C. 6, this /cat yap itceivos e(j)rj iravrav xpppdrav eivai perpov avdpa—ov, ovdev erepov \eyav rj to Sokovv incurra rovro /cat eivai irayias. It will be observed that in these accounts there is an interpretation put on the language of Protagoras. But there can be no doubt that Plato, and Aristotle too, laboured each in his own way to show, in op- position to these views, that there was a reality and a truth indepen- dent of the individual and of appearance. (See infra, Chap. III.) It is an instructive circumstance that the Sensationalist School has reached in our day the very position of the Sophists, and regard it as impossible to reach independent and necessary truth, if indeed any such truth exists. We might expect that such men would seek to justify the Sophists, and disparage the high arguments of Plato. Cudworth, speak- ing of the theoretical universal propositions in geometry and meta- physics, has finely remarked that it is true of every one of them when- ever “ it is rightly understood by any particular mind, whatsoever and wheresoever it be: the truth of it is no private thing, nor relative to that particular mind only, but is aikrjdes KadoXueov, ‘ a catholic and uni- versal truth,’ as the Stoics speak, throughout the whole world; nay, it would not fail to be a truth throughout infinite worlds, if there were so many, to all such minds as would rightly understand it” (Immutable Morality, bk. iv. c. v.). 5S GIIAIIACTER OF INTUITIONS. is a reality or is a truth; we know it to be so, we judge it to be so. And it is a reality, a truth, whether others know and acknowledge it or no. It is a truth, not merely to me or you, but to all men; not only to all men, but to all intelligences capable of discovering truths of that particular nature. That two lines cannot enclose a space, is a truth everywhere, in the planet Mars as well as in the planet Earth. That ingratitude is morally evil, must hold good in all other worlds, as well as in this world of ours, where sin so much abounds. Another misapprehension, of a different character, must also be rectified. 4. It is wrong to represent all our intuitive convic- tions as being formed within us from our birth. The account given of them by some would leave the impres- sion on the mind that they must all appear in infancy. This is commonly the view taken by those who throw ridicule upon them. What can be so preposterous, they say, as to suppose that babies are meditating on the in- finite from the time they escape from the womb, and distinguishing between good and evil before they know the right hand from the left ? The account which has been given, in these chapters, of our original convictions, shows how they may not all appear from our earliest years. They are formed, we have seen, on the contem- plation of objects presenting themselves from without or from within. Some of these objects press themselves, I believe, on the notice from the very first action of the soul, and the intuitions directed to these are exercised with the very first exercises of intelligence. From the very dawn of existence the infant must envisage self, and body acting on self. But there are other convic- tions which cannot be formed till a later date, because the objects to which they relate cannot be presented till the intelligence is advanced. Thus I believe that the MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 59 conviction of moral good and evil arises on the presen- tation of voluntary actions done by intelligent beings, and the mind must have made progress before it can form such a notion, and look into it to see what is in- volved in it. The intuition in regard to the infinite is called forth only when we contemplate such objects as space and time, or God, and the comprehension of these implies a considerable maturity of intelligence. We thus see that though all our intuitive convictions are native, yet some of them are the result of growth. Some of them do not appear in infancy ; some of them appear in chil- dren, and among persons low in the scale of understand- ing, such as savages, only in a very low and rudimen- tary form. All of them are capable of growing with the growth of our intelligence, and even with the growth of our voluntary and emotional nature. Some of them are at one and the same time natural, and the issue of a long development—like the flower and the fruit, which are in the plant from its embryo, but may not be actu- ally formed till there has been a stalk and branches, and leaves and buds. Sect. IY. Certain Practical Characteristics. From the theoretical characters there flow some others of a more practical nature. 1. All men who have had their attention addressed to the objects, are in fact led by spontaneous conviction, and this, whatever be their professed speculative opi- nions. This follows from the circumstance that they are self-evident, and that men, all men, must give their as- sent to them. The regulative principles being essential parts of man’s nature, we find all men under the influ- ence of them. Being irresistible, no man can deliver him- self from them. They are ever operating spontaneously, and that whether men do or do not acknowledge them CO CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. reflexly. In this respect the philosopher and the peasant, the dogmatist and the sceptic are at one. The metaphy- sician who has detected and formalized the principle, is not in a better position than the mechanic who acts on the principle without knowing that there is a principle. The sceptic who denies the principle is notwithstanding convinced of the individual truth when it is pressed upon his notice, quite as implicitly as the philosopher who is strenuously defending it. 2. These self-evident truths cannot be set aside by any other truth, real or pretended. They could be over- thrown only by some truth higher in itself, or carrying with it greater weight. But there is no such truth, there can be no such truth. There are indeed co-ordinate prin- ciples,—all self-evident truths are in respect of veracity of equal rank,—but not even on the supposition that the one contradicted the other, could we set aside either. The result in which such a contradiction should land us, is not a selection of one or other, but absolute scepti- cism, always along with implicit spontaneous faith in both principles. I shall have occasion to show that we are not landed in any such lamentable issue, and that all attempts to prove that intuitive truths contradict each other have lamentably failed. It follows that when an apparent contradiction arises between what seems a self-evident truth and any other supposed truth, we are to examine the evidence which we have for both. It is thus that the mathematician acts when his demonstrations seem to be contradictory. He does not allow himself to imagine that truth can be inconsistent; he goes over his demonstrations to find out what error he has himself committed. If one funda- mental principle seems to be inconsistent with another fundamental principle, we are to examine whether both are certainly fundamental, and can be shown to be so MARKS AND PECULIARITIES. 61 by the proper tests, and in particular whether they have been properly generalized and expressed. In all such cases it will be found either that one at least of the principles is not intuitively certain—indeed neither of them may be so; or, as is more common, we may not have properly stated the primitive principle, and the seeming inconsistency lies not in the principles them- selves, but in our expression of them. Or, again, the apparent contradiction may lie between a primitive principle and a derivative one. In such a case it is certain that if what seems a primitive principle be truly so, and if we have put it in the proper form, it can never be displaced or overthrown by any secondary one. For if we follow that derivative principle to its foundation, we shall find that it cannot be resting on any truth more authoritative than the fundamental one which it is now being employed to undermine, while in the derivation of it, a number of doubtful elements may have entered which must render it by more or fewer de- grees less certain than the intuitive truth against which it is set. In all such cases we must examine the sup- posed first principle, to see that it is a first principle, and that it is properly inducted, and review the deri- vative principle in order to determine the nature of the evidence by which it is supported. By such a sifting process the seeming contradiction vV:U in all probability disappear; but if it still continue, we are of course shut up to the alternative of adhering to the fundamental truth, and laying aside the derivative one, as being in- ferior in authority and certainty. 62 CHAPTER II. METHOD OF EMPLOYING INTUITIVE PRINCIPLES. Sect. I. The Spontaneous and Reflex Use of Intuitive Principles. From the account which has been given of the Intuitions, it appears that they may operate—indeed they are ever operating—of their own accord, and without our prompt- ing them into exercise by any voluntary act; and it ap- pears, too, that we may generalize the individual actings, discover the rule of their operation, and then proceed to use them in deduction and in speculation. The former of these may be called the Spontaneous Action, and the latter the Reflex Application of the Intuitions. In their spontaneous exercise they are regulating principles, regu- lating thought and belief, and operating whether we ob- serve them or no. But in this operation our convictions all relate to singulars, and so cannot be directly used in philosophic speculation. In order to their scientific ap- plication, there is need of careful reflex observation and generalization. In order to their spontaneous perception it is not requisite that their nature should be determined, they act best when we look simply at the object and take no introspection of them. But to a legitimate applica- tion of them in philosophy, it is essential that their exact nature, and precise law and rule, be carefully determined. It is all-important, in treating of our intuitions, to draw such a distinction, for much which may be affirmed of them under one of these aspects cannot be affirmed of them in the other.* * “La raison se developpe de deux manieres, spontaneity et re- G3 METHOD OF APPLICATION. 1. The spontaneous must always precede the reflex form. We have already noticed the circumstance that in the ease of some of them the spontaneous perception begins with the earliest exercise of the intelligence, while in the case of others, though a preparation is made for them from the beginning—just as all the organs of the animal may be said to be in the embryo—it is long before they come out in open manifestation, and in unfavour- able circumstances they may never appear in a fully de- veloped form, or in vigorous life. But at whatever time they appear spontaneously, the generalized expression of them must always be later. We cannot generalize them till we have observed them, and we cannot ob- serve them till they are in exercise. The reflex use of them is a scientific process, and cannot begin in the in- dividual or in a nation, till the scientific spirit has been engendered. Even in their native form, some of them appear only in the mature man and in the fully developed mind; in their reflex shape they are found only in indi- viduals and in ages and countries addicted to reflection or inward observation. Indeed, as the discovery, or even the comprehension, of the reflex law implies a special bending back of the eye, from which most men shrink, the process is one which the great mass of mankind never engage in, and which the majority of those who engage in it never follow, except for the sustaining of some favourite dogma, or the repelling of some proffered objection. It must be late in the history of inquiry and flexion.”—“ La raison debute par une syntbese ricbe et feconde, mais obscure: vient apres F analyse qui eclaircit tout en divisant tout, et qui aspire eUe-meme a une syntbese superieure, aussi comprehensive que la premiere et plus lumineuse. La spontaneite donne la verite; la re- flexion produit la science ; l’une fournit une base large et solide aux developpements de l’bumanite; l’autre imprime a ces developpements leur forme la plus parfaite.”—“ L’erreur vient de la reflexion.” (Cousin, Cours de l’Hist. Pbil. lle serie, t. i. vi. vii.) 64 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. speculation before we can expect to have an expression of the laws of the intuitions expounded simply for its scientific value, or as a body of scientific truth. 2. The intuition, in its reflex, abstract, or general form, is derived from, and is best tested by, the concrete spon- taneous conviction. In order to the formation of the definition, maxim, or axiom, we must have objects or cases before us, and we must be careful to observe them, and note what is involved in them. It is a matter of fact that geometry arose out of men- suration. Men began by measuring fields and heights, and thence proceeded to construct a scientific mode of accomplishing what had been done by practical rules, and I suspect that the enunciation of axioms and some of the more elementary demonstrations, came at a later date than practical rules, or even than certain of the more advanced propositions. We find, in like manner, that a systematized and connected Ethics, proceeding from ori- ginal principles, and going on to applications, came later in the history of moral philosophy than the practical in- junctions of parents, or the moral codes of legislators and the laws of religion. There was reasoning, and even rules of reasoning, before a regular Logic appeared. Me- taphysics has arisen out of the contests of opposing sects, or has been interposed as a breakwater against a tide of scepticism. In all times and circumstances, the most effectual means of testing logical, ethical, and metaphysical prin- ciple, is by the application of it to actual cases, which should be as numerous and varied as possible. It is when actual examples are before it that the mind is able to appreciate the meaning of the general formulae. It is only when it has considered them in their application to a number of diversified instances that the mind is in circumstances to pronounce them to be probably, or METHOD OF APPLICATION. Go approximately, or altogether correct.* Without such observational testiug, definition, division, arrangement, and deduction may have rather a tempting and mislead- ing influence. A power of dissection and inference can do as little in metaphysical as in physical investigation, that is, it is of no value at all, or may be positively inju- rious unless it proceed on a previous collation of facts. Minds of great logical and critical discernment are apt to go further wrong than others who are no philosophers at all, by seizing on some mutilated or imperfectly ex- pressed principle, and carrying it out fearlessly, according to the rules of a rigid deduction. Of all men, those who live in the region of high abstractions, which they never bring down to realities, are most apt to go astray as in snow-drift; and when they do wander, they go faster and further wrong than other men. At the same time, it is to be observed that the ab- straction, or generalization, is not got from an outward object or event which may fall under ocular inspection or instrumental experiment, but from the operations of a mental law, which may be altogether missed by those who are exclusively engrossed with the object at which the mind is looking when the regulative principle is working. Of all men, the ardent sense-observer, or the * Kant has laid down a very different maxim, declaring that exam- ples only injure the understanding in respect of the correctness and precision of the apprehension. Speaking of examples : “ Denn was die Richtigkeit und Precision der Yerstandeseinsicht betrifft, so thun sie derselben vielmehr gemeiniglich einigen Abbruch, weil sie nur selten die Bedingung der Regel adaquat erfiillen (als casus in terminis), und iiberdies diejenige Anstrengung des Verstandes oftmals schwachen, Regeln im Allgemeinen, und unabhangig von den besonderen Umstan- den der Erfahrung, nach ihrer Zulanglichkeit, einzusehen, und sie daher zuletzt mehr wie Eormeln, als Gfrundsatze, zu gebrauchen angewohnen ” (K. d. r. Yern. Trans. Log., p. 119: Rosen.). This shows that Kant had no correct idea of the way in which the general rule is reached. The same view is evidently taken by many of the formal logicians of our day. 66 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. lively picturer of external images, is the most inclined to shrink from reflex inspection, and is the worst fitted to propound or to judge of abstract mental principles. 3. The expression of the abstract or general truth is more or less easy, and is likely to be more or less correct, according to the simplicity of the objects to which the spontaneous conviction is directed. It is evident that some of the intuitive principles of the mind are more difficult to detect and formalize than others. Those which are directed to sensible objects, and simple ob- jects, will be found out more easily, and at an earlier date, than those which look to more complex or spiritual objects. Thus the intuitions regarding space—seen by the eye, and readily pictured in the imagination—were abstracted, and generalized into geometrical definitions and axioms, at an early stage of intellectual culture. It is a vastly more difficult task to express accurately, and in their ultimate form, the intuitive convictions regard- ing such objects as substance, and quality, and the laws involved in thought and moral perception. Still the war of contending sects, and the assaults of the sceptic, and the insidious underminings of the sophist, would compel men, at an early date, to evolve some sort of logic, and we have the nature of genera and species and definition, chalked out by Socrates, the principle of contradiction employed by Plato, and the formula of reasoning deter- mined, at least approximately, by Aristotle, and, in a looser form, even in India, more than two thousand years ago.* The practical interest collecting round moral ques- tions would also lead to an early enunciation of ethical principle, which, however, owing to the innumerable re- lations involved in the discharge of duty, would not, at an early stage, take a thoroughly fundamental or rigidly * See Paper on Indian Logie, by Professor Max Muller, in Appen- dix to Thompson’s ‘ Outline of the Laws of Thought.’ METHOD OF APPLICATION. 07 exact form. The crude nature of the classification em- bodied in the cardinal virtues, is a proof of the difficulty of expressing the ultimate laws of morality, or the su- preme rule of right and wrong. A similar complexity presents itself in all inquiries in which substance and force enter as elements, and hence, while attempts will be made from the commencement of speculation to ex- press first principles in regard to such objects, the rule announced will in general combine a mixture of intuitive and experiential elements, will be able to serve only a provisional purpose, will seldom be more than approxi- mately correct, and will require to be rectified by much subsequent examination and comparison with concrete cases. 4. In their spontaneous action the intuitions never err, properly speaking; but there may be manifold errors lurking in their reflex form and application. I have used the qualified language that properly speaking they do not err in their original impulses ; for even here they may carry error with them. They look to a representation given them, and this representation may be erroneous, and this error will appear in the result. The mind intui- tively declares that on a real quality presenting itself, it must imply a substance; but what is not truly a quality may be represented as a quality, and then it is declared that this quality implies a substance. Thus Sir Isaac Newton and I)r. S. Clarke represented time and space as qualities, (which I regard as a mistake,) and then repre- sented reason as guaranteeing that these qualities implied a substance in which they inhere, which is God. But the error in such cases cannot legitimately be charged on the intuition, which is exercised simply in regard to the presentation or representation made to it. But there is room for innumerable errors creeping into the abstract or general enunciation and the scientific ap- 68 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. plication of it. For we may have made a most defective, or exaggerated, or totally inaccurate abstraction or gene- ralization of the formula out of the individual exercises, or we may apply it to cases to which it has no legitimate reference. From such causes as these have sprung those oversights, exaggerations, and not unfrequently flagrant and pernicious errors, which have appeared in every form of metaphysical speculation. This is a topic which will fall to be resumed in next Section. 5. The tests of intuitive convictions admit of an ap- plication to the abstract and general principle, only so far as the abstraction and generalization have been pro- perly performed. It is only as applied to singulars, that our perceptions can be regarded as intuitive. The tests of intuitions, viz. self-evidence, necessity, and catholicity, apply directly only to individual convictions. To the formalized expression of them, the tests apply only me- diately, and on the supposition and condition that the formulae are the proper expression of the spontaneous convictions. It is always possible that the abstraction and the generalization have not been correctly executed. In some cases, this is no more than barely possible. When- ever the object is a very simple one, presenting itself very much apart from all other circumstances, there is scarcely the possibility of error creeping in. Hence the assur- ance which the mind feels in regard to mathematical axioms, and the propositions founded on them by steps every one of which is intuitive. Even in regard to mathe- matics there may be doubts and contests, but it is only in more recondite topics, such for instance as those into which the idea of infinity enters. But in regard to intui- tions which refer to objects which are more complicated, that is, which are mixed up with divers other matters in our comprehension, there may be difficulties in exactly METHOD OF APPLICATION. 69 seizing and expressing the principle, and there may there- fore be doubts and disputes as to whether any given ac- count of them is correct and adequate. It is self-evi- dent as to this particular quality, that it implies a sub- stance, but there is much obscurity about the general relation of substance and quality. The mind at once declares of this given effect that it must have a cause, but there may be doubts and difficulties as to the proper form in which to put the law of causation. Every man is convinced that he is the same person today as he was yesterday, but how few have had consciously before them the general principle of self and of personality ! Sect. II. Sources of Error in Metaphysical Speculation. All proposed metaphysical principles are attempted expressions of the intuitions in the form of a general law. Now error may at times spring from the assump- tion of a principle which has no existence whatever in the human mind. I am persuaded however that the errors thus originated are comparatively few, and are seldom followed by serious consequences. In regard to the assumption of totally imaginary principles, I am con- vinced that there have been fewer mistakes in metaphy- sical than in physical science. As the intuitions of the mind are working in every man’s bosom, it will seldom happen that the speculator can set out with a principle which has no existence whatever; and should he so ven- ture, he would certainly meet with little response. It is possible also for error to arise from a chain of erroneous deduction from principles which are genuine in them- selves and soundly interpreted. The mistakes springing from this quarter are likewise, I believe, few and trifling, the more so that those who draw such inferences are generally men of powerful logical mind, and not likely 70 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. to commit errors in reasoning; and if they did, those who have ability to follow them would be sure to detect them. By far the most copious source of error in philosophic speculation is to be found in the imperfect, or exagger- ated, or mutilated expression of principles which really have a place in our constitution. In such cases the pre- sence of the real metal gives currency to the dross which is mixed with it. In regard to many of our intuitions, the gathering of the common quality out of the concrete and individual manifestations is about as subtle a work as the human understanding can engage in. This arises from the re- condite, the complicated, and fugitive nature of the mental states, from which they must be drawn. But from the very commencement of speculation and the breaking out of discussion, attempts have been made to give a body and a form to the native convictions. It is seldom that the account is altogether illusory; most commonly there is a basis of fact to set off the fiction. But the prin- ciple is seen and represented only under one aspect, while others are left out of sight. It oft.ens happens that he whose intuitions are the strongest and the liveliest is of all men the least qualified to examine and generalize them, and should he be tempted to embody them in proposi- tions, they will be sure to take distorted, perhaps errone- ous forms. In all departments of speculation, metaphy- sical, ethical, and theological, we meet with persons whose faith is strong, whose sentiments are fervent, and whose very reason is far-seeing, but whose creed—that is, forma- lized doctrine—is extravagant, or even perilously wrong. In other cases the conviction, genuine in itself, is put forth in a mutilated shape by prejudiced men to support a favourite doctrine, or by party men to get rid of a for- midable objection. The human mind is impelled by an intellectual craving, METHOD OF APPLICATION. 71 and by the circumstances in which it is placed, to be ever generalizing, and this in respect both of material and mental phenomena. But its earliest classes and systems, even those of them made for scientific purposes, are com- monly of a very crude character. Still, even such genera- lizations, though at the best mere approximations, at times serve valuable ends in the absence of better and until better appear. Such laws as these have been laid down, “ Nature abhors a vacuum;” “ Some bodies are naturally light, and others heavy“ Combustible bodies are che- mically composed of a base with phlogiston combined with it“ The organs of the flower are transformed leaves.” These were the best general statements which scientific inquirers could give at the time of their obser- vations. They served to express, if not to explain, cer- tain phenomena. Nature’s horror of a vacuum showed how water rose in a pump. The doctrine of the na- tural heaviness and lightness of bodies seemed to explain how stones fell to the earth, while smoke rose in the atmosphere. The burning of brimstone was thought to be satisfactorily accounted for, when it was said that brimstone being composed of sulphurous acid and phlo- giston, the combustion consisted in giving out phlogiston. The undoubted correspondence between the leaf and the stamen suggested the idea that the leaf had been trans- formed into a stamen. But modern science, advancing in the inductive method, has shown that none of these were correct expressions of the real laws of nature. It cannot be because of its aversion to a vacuum, that water rises in a pump, for if the vacuum extends higher than a certain number of feet, the water allows it to exist in its emptiness. Smoke rises from the earth, not because of its natural levity, but because it is buoyed up by the atmosphere. It unfortunately happens that lead, after it is burned,—that is, after it has given off, accord- 72 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. ing to the phlogiston theory, one of its ingredients,—is found to be heavier than before. Stamens and pistils have never been leaves, they are merely after the same model. These are examples from physical science. Metaphysical science, from the subtle and intertwined nature of the phe- nomena, can furnish far more numerous instances. In the mental sciences the general statements have commonly a genuine fact, but mixed with this there is often an alloy. The error may not influence the spontaneous action of the primitive principle, but it may tell terribly in the reflex application. It may not even exercise any prejudicial influence in certain departments of investigation, but in other walks it may work endless confusion, or land in consequences fitted to sap the very foundations of morality and religion. Take the distinction drawn, in some form, by most civilized languages, between the head and the heart. The distinction embodies a great truth, and when used in conversation or popular discourse it can conduct to no evil. But it cannot be carried out psychologically. For in each a number of very distinct faculties are included. Under the phrase ‘ heart,5 in particular, are covered powers with wide diversities of function, such as the conscience, the emotions, and the will. The question agitated in this century, whether religion be an affair of the head or the heart, has come to be a hopelessly perplexed one, because the offices of the powers embraced under each are di- verse, and run into each other; and certain of the posi- tions taken up are, to say the least of it, perilous : as when it is said that religion resides exclusively in the heart, and persons understand that it is a matter of mere emo- tion, omitting understanding, will, and conscience, which have equally a part to play. Of the same description is the distinction between the reason and the understand- ing. It points to a reality. There is a distinction between reason in its primary, and reason in its secondary or METHOD OF APPLICATION. 73 logical exercises, and the mind can rise, always however by a process in which the logical understanding is em- ployed, to the discovery of universal and necessary truth. But each of the divisions, the reason and the understand- ing, comprises powers which run into each other. This distinction is at the best confusing,* and it is often so stated as to imply that the reason, without the use of the understanding processes of abstraction and generaliza- tion, can rise to the contemplation of the true, the beau- tiful, and the good. It can be shown that some of the ancient philosophers, and Kepler in modern times, had glimpses of a law of universal gravitation before the days of Newton, but none of these had been able to determine its exact nature and rule. Suppose that while science was at this stage, some person had affirmed that there was a power of at- traction among all bodies, varying inversely not according to the square of the distance, but according to the distance : he would no doubt have had a truth, and a very important one ; but the law thus stated, while it explained in a ge- neral way a number of the phenomena, would, when de- ductions were drawn from it, have issued in ever accumu- lating errors, and this not because no such law existed, but because its rule had been improperly apprehended and enunciated. Almost all metaphysical errors spring from this source, from the improper formalization of principles which are real laws of our constitution. When presented in this mutilated shape, even truth may lead to hideous consequences. It will be shown as we advance that there is an intuitive law of cause and effect, but this law has not always been correctly enunciated. Suppose it be put in this form, that “ Everything must have a cause it will issue logically and necessarily in the result that the * This distinction is examined, Part III. Book I. Chap. II. sect. v.} Supplementary. 74 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. Intelligent Cause of this world must Himself have had a cause. This consequence can at once be avoided by a proper enunciation of the law of causation. We may now see how it is that metaphysicians, when they go wrong, go further wrong than others. This proceeds from the fundamental nature of metaphysical principles : every error here, like a mistake in taking- down the datum of an arithmetical or mathematical ques- tion, must issue in fearfully magnified error in the results reached. This weakness in the foundation must make the structure insecure to its topmost pinnacle. The tainting of the fountain will go with the stream in all its length. Suppose that we set out in ethical discussion, with the assumption that virtue is just a far-sighted love of pleasure; or in theology, with the dogma that justice is a modification of benevolence: it will turn out that these principles (which I believe to be wrong) will affect the whole superstructure of speculation, and lead those who adopt them to take very inadequate views of sin on the one hand, and the justice of God on the other. It should be added, that an error in the starting principle comes out in more exaggerated errors in the issue, in very proportion to the rigid consecutiveness of the de- duction, and the extent to which it is carried. A mistake in the first steps of an arithmetical question, may be lessened by some counterbalancing blunder in the further calculations. It has often happened that philosophers have shrunk from following out their prin- ciples to their consequences. Locke in particular has often been saved from extreme opinions to which his theory led, but from which his sagacity and honesty re- coiled, by falling into inconsequences and inconsistencies. Powerful logical minds, like Spinoza and Hegel, have, on the other hand, boldly avowed the most extravagant doc- trines, as being the legitimate result of their gratuitous assumptions. METHOD OF APPLICATION. 75 There is another circumstance to be taken into ac- count by those who would unfold the theory of the meta- physician’s extravagancies; he is not restrained as the physical investigator is by stubborn facts, nor checked as the commercial man is by stern realities, which he dare not despise. He has only to mount into a region of pure (or rather, I should say, cloudy), speculation to find himself in circumstances to cleave his way with- out meeting with any felt barrier. At the same time one might have reasonably expected, that when such speculators as Spinoza, Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, felt themselves rushing headlong against all acknowledged truth, they would have suspected that there was some- thing wrong in their assumptions, or in their method. Whenever the results reached contradict the senses or the established doctrines of physical science, whenever they lead to the denial of the distinction between good and evil, or the personality of the soul, or of the exist- ence, the personality, and continual providence of God, it is time to review the process by which they have been gained, for they are running counter to truths which have too deep a foundation to be moved by doubtful speculations. The remark of Bacon as to physical, may be applied to metaphysical speculation, that doctrine is to be tried by fruits. “ Of all signs there is none more certain or worthy than that of the fruits produced; for the fruits and effects are sureties and vouchers, as it were, for philosophy.” “ In the same manner as we are cau- tioned by religion to show our faith by our works, we may freely apply the principle to philosophy, and judge of it by its works, accounting that to be futile which is unproductive, and still more, if instead of grapes and olives it yield but the thistles and thorns of dispute and contention.” 76 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. Sect. III. Conditions of the Legitimacy of the Appeal to Intuitive Principles. There is scarcely occasion to lay down any rules as to the spontaneous use of the regulative principles of the mind. It is of their nature to act, and, like the physiological processes of seeing and breathing, they act all the better when no notice is taken of them. All that is necessary to call them forth is to present the appro- priate objects ;—in mathematics, for example, to present geometrical figures and quantities, and in moral sub- jects to present models and ideals of excellence. Thus are they evoked in the first instance, and thus are our intellectual and moral intuitions refined, elevated, and strengthened. Any other rules fitted to promote their right action are of a moral, rather than a speculative character. If the motive power of the mind be right, if the man be impelled by a love of truth, and swayed by a spirit of candour, then the regulative principles, if occupied about the proper objects, will of themselves perform their proper function. There is truth in the common observation that a mind sophisticated by logic and confused by metaphysics will often fall into errors from which others who follow only good sense and good feeling are happily delivered. But if persons wish at any time to review their opi- nions, or answer objections, or convince others by argu- ment, they must employ principles of some kind, and these, in the last resort, must conduct to first principles. I suppose that if man’s moral nature had been pure, he would never have fallen into error; there would have been no difference among mankind in regard to ques- tions of vital moment, and controversy would have been unknown. In such a happy condition, I believe that first principles would have been contemplated simply as METHOD OF APPLICATION. 77 a matter of intellectual curiosity, and as illustrative of the Divine wisdom. It is not necessary to prove that man is not placed in such a blessed state of things. It is scarcely possible to find three men met together whose opinions are at one, even on essential points; to err is an inherent weakness of humanity, and some have fallen into most pernicious mistakes. Every man needs, in consequence, to examine the apprehensions he has formed, and the convictions which he has been led to entertain; he has to defend what he believes to be truth when it is assailed, and he has, in a spirit of love, to endeavour to convince others of their errors when these relate to matters of great moment for this life or the life to come. In this world of ours, the review of impressions and opinions, and discussion, are matters of absolute neces- sity : but this implies the use of proofs, premisses, tests; and if we pursue these sufficiently far (as we must at times be constrained to do), we go beyond derivative to original principles. But are we allowed to call in a supposed fundamental principle when it suits us, or use it in the form we please, to justify an opinion to which we are determined to adhere at all hazards, or to crush our opponent ? As there are logical rules to guard against abuse in derivative argument, so there may also be logical rules laid down to restrain the appeal to assumable pre- misses. 1. Those who appeal to first truths must be prepared to show that they are first truths. In most investiga- tions it is not necessary ever to be going down to the foundation. In ordinary physical inquiry, for example, we may assume such laws as gravitation and chemical affinity, without being required to prove them once and and again. But in certain discussions, theological and philosophical, more especially when the controversy is with the doubter or the sceptic, it may be needful to rest 78 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. our first stones on the foundation, —in all such cases we must be sure that we have gone down to the rock. We must hold ourselves ready to prove, not indeed the truth of the first principle,—for this is impossible in the nature of things,—but that it is a first principle. We are re- quired to show that it is self-evident; and if this be de- nied, we may show that we are constrained to believe it, and cannot be made to judge or decide the contradic- tory of it to be true; and we may confirm all this by showing that all men adhere to it. We should not stop short of this in the argument which we construct for our own conviction. An opponent has a right to insist on this in arguing with us on questions which go down to the bottom; and we have a right, in arguing with one who makes any appeal to primary principles, to demand of him to prove that what he is calling in be in fact a self-evident and necessary conviction. 2. Those who employ intuitive principles in demon- stration, speculation, or discussion of any kind, must see that they accurately express them. This is done in the science of geometry, which owes much of its certainty, and the satisfaction which the mind feels in contempla- ting its truths, to the circumstance that it begins with announcing, in the rigid form of axioms, or postulates, all that it assumes. We should insist that the same be done in all other branches which employ first prin- ciples. The canon is, not only that they be enunciated, but that their precise rule be enunciated. It often hap- pens that in the popular expression of material facts, a law is put in a form which gives some information, but which may not after all be absolutely correct. People often say that mountains draw the clouds, and thus foster rain, and this gives a sort of statement of certain facts; but the true account is that the cold mountain condenses the moisture in the current of air sweeping over it. It METHOD OF APPLICATION. 79 is quite right to say that the tides are produced by the attraction of the moon, and this explains some of the facts; but then it cannot show how there is full tide not only on the side of the earth next the moon, but on the opposite side. In the expression of the phenomena of the mind, there are still more frequent instances of statements which are only approximately correct. Thus substance has been explained as that which subsists of itself, or needs nothing else in order to its existence. This account contains a truth, but is expressed in too unrestricted a form. Spinoza, proceeding on such a de- finition, which had been supplied him by the school of Descartes, goes on with a bristling array of forms, and much w~ord-quibbling, to demonstrate, that there can be only one substance, of which all other things are the attributes or modes. We are at once saved from this pantheistic consequence by putting the proper limitation on the definition. It is quite true that in all discussion, theological and moral, philosophic principles are often ap- pealed to, and may serve a proper purpose, even when not very formally or accurately expressed. This they do because the truth contained in the principle happens to be applicable. But it might have happened to be other- wise. “Every event has a cause:” this is a maxim which we are applying in our every-day reasonings and observations. But has it no limits ? or is causation of the same character in regard to every event ? In par- ticular, does causation reign in the will, as it reigns in the material universe ? or if it does, is causation in the will the same in kind as causation in external nature, or as causation in the intelligence? He who uses the principle of causation indiscriminately, may, before he is aware of it, land himself in the conclusion that man is as much the slave of circumstances as every spoke in the wheel, or as every link in a chain, which a strong force 80 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. is dragging along. We can save ourselves from such consequences only by limiting, modifying, or explaining the doctrine of causation. We have already seen that our intuition regarding causality may be so stated as to land us in an infinite series of causes; we now see that it may be so enounced as to undermine the great moral doctrine of the essential freedom of the will. We see how important it must be to have the nature and the precise range of the law clearly and definitely settled. The two rules now laid down may seem to some to be very hard ones; but they are very necessary ones to arrest those confused and confusing controversies which abound to such an extent in philosophy, in theology, and in other departments of investigation as well. It is al- ways indeed to be allowed that our inquiries on most subjects may be conducted and terminated satisfactorily without our being required to go down to metaphysical principles. The farmer, the merchant, the politician, and even the physical investigator in most of his walks, may come to the right conclusion in regard to the topics which they wish to settle, without its being necessary for them to determine the nature of mathematical axioms or the law of cause and effect; on which, notwithstand- ing, some of these calculations regarding the seasons or the tides or the movements of the heavenly bodies, or the probable actings of men, may after all depend—only, however, in the sense of a deep foundation which it is not necessary for these parties to examine. But if any one will enter on speculations involving radical truth, he must be prepared to submit to the conditions on which they can be properly conducted. No man is bound to be a metaphysician unless he chooses, but if he insist on becoming one, he must attend to the rules of the office which he takes on himself. Every man is not under a moral obligation to throw aside other useful pursuits, and METHOD OF APPLICATION. 81 devote himself to answering such speculations as those of Spinoza, Berkeley, Hume, Fichte, or Hegel; but if he ventures into the arena, he must conform to its rules. Every friend of religion is not obliged to write a philo- sophic defence of it, and some who have ventured upon such a work might have been more profitably employed in some less ambitious undertaking, as in defending some of the outworks of religion, or illustrating its power by their lives ; but those who claim to be philosophers must comport themselves as philosophers. It is to be regretted that multitudes dabble in metaphysics who have no ca- pacity for grappling with its subtle truths ; but the only effective mode of curbing this incompetency and quack- ery, is by insisting on all those who would enter the trade undergoing some sort of scientific apprenticeship or process of training. Nor are these restrictions the less necessary from the circumstance that not a few of those who possess the greatest aversion to metaphysics are all the while deep in metaphysics without their know- ing it, and certainly without their being prepared to avow it, and it is necessary to lay an arrest on such by show- ing what the science is, and compelling them if they en- ter the country to conform to its laws. There are persons who are constrained by the circum- stances in which they are placed, or by what they believe to be the voice of duty, to discuss fundamental questions. There have been persons, even in the lowest walks of life, troubled, owing to a peculiar intellectual tempera- ment (commonly not of a very healthy character), with speculative doubts, which are only to be removed by speculative arguments; but, if convinced, it must surely be by arguments built on a sure foundation. • Some are placed in a position in which they are assailed by the in- fidel, and feel that they must meet him in the cause of truth and religion. Some, as knowing that they possess 82 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. peculiar gifts, feel themselves called on to defend the very citadel of morals or of religion, or to rear a fabric of truth compacted from the very base. But if these men are not to waste their strength in a war of subtle- ties, they must be careful how they begin to build, lest what they rear turn out to be crazy and unstable, and a source of weakness rather than of strength. Paying at- tention to certain restrictions and precautions themselves, they will be in a position to insist on wild speculators, or the sceptics whom they oppose, conforming themselves to these canons ot the logic of metaphysical speculation. These then I reckon as the conditions of all argument which appeals formally to primary truth, to necessary conviction, or common sense. Persons not pretending to be philosophers, and discussing none of those topics which philosophers alone can discuss, may claim the pri- vilege, when a sceptical objection comes in their way, or an altogether unbelievable dogma is asserted, of reject- ing it at once, on the ground of spontaneous conviction, and troubling themselves no more about it. They must take care, however, in all -such cases, that what they sup- pose to be a native conviction be not a mere preposses- sion of education, or prejudice of temper, and if there be ground for doubt, there is no help for it but in an appeal to the tests of intuitions, and the canons of their legitimate use. And as to those who profess to proceed philoso- phically, it is incumbent on them that they prove that what they assume is an original conviction, and that they generalize the spontaneous exercises, and express them in rigid formulae. But when it is thus conducted, the ar- gument from intuition or common sense is not an argu- rnentum ad populmn, and least of all an argument ad- dressed to vulgar prejudice. It presupposes a rigid sci- entific process, and should not be attempted by any ex- cept those who possess the requisite retrospective powers METHOD OF APPLICATION. 83 of observation, and have disciplined themselves to the rules of the logic of first principles. When conformed to the right conditions, it is an argument strictly scien- tific, eminently satisfactory within its proper domain, and is in an especial sense the philosophical argument. Such restrictions as these would, I know full well, lay an arrest at once on more than one-half of the metaphy- sics of this age, and of every age. This would be felt to be a discouragement by certain eager youths, full of expectations of the results to be reached by philosophic speculation, and by certain older, but not wiser men, who have mapped out the whole intellectual globe, and would feel troubled at the idea of their distribution be- ing disturbed: but in the end there would be no loss; for the part remaining after the refining process, would be of vastly more worth, and would soon be acknow- ledged to be so. When speculative philosophy is pursued in the usual unrestrained manner, the results reached are of the most unsatisfactory character, and at times are felt to be so. How often do ardent youths rush into the country opened to them, as keenly as the adventurers in the sixteenth century set out in search of El Dorado, and after spend- ing years, and wasting the strength of manhood, they come back with a sense of emptiness and a feeling of disappointment! Even those who refuse to abandon the hope, and who cling most resolutely to the idea that they have discovered genuine gold, are now and again all but overwhelmed with a feeling of prostration and bitterness, and break out, as the Doctor in £ Faust,’— “ I feel it, I have heaped upon my brain The gathered treasure of man’s thought in vain.” In such there is a weariness, an aching, an ennui of the head, which is felt to be as deep, if not so keen, as the aching, the ennui of the heart ever is; and yet there may 84 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. coexist with this a determination to continue the fruit- less pursuit. Others have had a confession wrung from them like that of Jacobi: “ In my younger years it stood thus with me in regard to philosophy: I seemed to myself to be heir to innumerable riches, and only some unim- portant lawsuits and some unmeaning formalities seemed to hinder me from taking full possession of my inheri- tance. The suits, while pending, grew to be important. At last it appeared that I had inherited nothing but lawsuits, and that the whole bequest was in insolvent hands.” Happy are those who advance, or who can return, as fresh in spirit and as innocent as when they entered. Some, feeling as if no certainty could be reached, or as if, after unwinding the folds of the mystery, nothing wonderful or worthy has been discovered, have come to the settled conclusion that it is vain for them ever after to expect to find certainty, to reach felt assurance, or even to look for anything worth seeing, and so give them- selves up to listlessness and apathy. Wandering till they have become bewildered, as if in a deep and gloomy fo- rest, they sit down with the intention of never rising; or, like persons wearied and worn out in snowdrift, they lie down to become benumbed, and are ready to perish in cold. Still worse consequences have followed. How often does the eager youth rush on till he falls into the abyss!— “ He eagerly pursues, Beyond the realms of dreams, that fleeting shade; He overleaps the bounds !” Entering into the labyrinth, to survey its wonders, he is lost in its numberless passages and its endless wind- ings, without being ever able to find his way back to the open light and air; nay, how often has it happened that the builder of such intricacies has himself been METHOD OF APPLICATION. 85 imprisoned and entombed within them. Or, rushing eagerly to solve the sphinx riddles which Nature is pro- pounding, and unable to find the solution, he must pay the awful penalty to that terrible Power, which insists on a reply, and crushes those who try and do not suc- ceed ! Some have entered, with lively anticipations, this temple of mystery, only to come out oppressed with doubt, or with the language of scorn and scepticism on their lips; they have seen all, they say, been in the very Holy of Holies, and found it empty, with no God dwell- ing between the Cherubim or uttering his voice in the Shechinah. “ He dropped his plummet down the broad Deep universe, and said, ‘Ho God,’ Finding no bottom.” Sect. IV. Method of Investigating and Interpreting our Intuitions. Two questions require to be answered in all meta- physical investigation. The one is, What is the nature of the intuition itself? and the other, What is the nature of the object at which it looks, and for which it is the guarantee ? These two inquiries are to be prosecuted in one and the same way,—that is, in the method of in- duction ; not with sense, but consciousness, as our infor- mant. There is really no other manner of determining the nature of the intuitional power, its law, rule, and manner of operation; nor any other mode of ascertain- ing what is the kind of object or truth revealed by that power. I know of no shorthand or summary way, by logic or cogitation, of settling these two essential ques- tions in philosophy. It might have been different if man had been conscious of the intuition as an intuition. In this case it would only have been needful to look within by the internal sense in order to find its nature. 86 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. But just as the law of gravitation is not written on the face of the sky so that the eye can see it, so neither is the law of causation printed on the soul so that con- sciousness can read off the inscription. The one law, like the other, is to be ascertained by an investigation of its individual acts, and this in a state of things in which the action of one property is closely interblended with that of another property; necessitating not only an observation of facts, but a very patient and discerning induction, so that we may catch the rule of the distinct agencies. The task, so far as the second question is concerned, might have been easier if all our intuitions had been con- structed so as to discover one and the same kind of truth. But as each of the senses is organized to discover its own kind of material qualities, so each of the internal percep- tions reveals its peculiar object or truth, and in its own peculiar manner. As inductive inquiry into the nature of perception through the eye will not settle for us what is the nature of perception through the touch, so neither can an investigation of any one intuition settle for us the nature of the apprehension which the others, or any of the others, are fitted to furnish. The metaphysician, in conducting his delicate inquiries, must go over the in- tuitions one by one, asking of each what it has to say of itself, and what is the vision which it has to disclose; in this respect acting like the divine who has the proper respect for revelation, and who does not determine be- forehand what the inspired record should say, but reve- rently asks, What saith the Scripture? A thousand errors have arisen in philosophy from omitting to look at our intuitions one by one, and from affirming of all what may be true only of some. It is the special office of the metaphysician to go to our intuitions one by one, and ask, What does it say of 87 METHOD OF APPLICATION. itself? what does it profess to look at and discover? This latter is the inquiry which we should make when our aim is to discover whether the conviction testifies to the exist- ence of an object or truth external to, or independent of, the mind perceiving it. To give some examples. What, we may ask, is the object attested by the mind when it is perceiving through the senses? The answer seems to be, an object external to self, extended and movable. In this exercise, and in every other intelligent exercise, con- sciousness testifies to the existence of a self in intelligent exercise. There are other operations in which the mind is simply imagining: even in such cases it has a know- ledge ; but it has no knowledge of, or belief in, an object external to the mind. If I am picturing a griffin, I am conscious of self thus engaged, but I have no intuitive conviction of the existence of a griffin, independent of my thinking of it, as I have of the existence of a pen or table when I press my hand upon it. In the interpreta- tion of the intuition, it is essential to inquire what, if any, is the sort of object to the existence of which it testifies. These two are different from yet another, and a third in- quiry -. Does, or does not, the intuition speak the truth ? Is it not possible that it may deceive us ? I am anxious to avoid this question for the present, and defer it till we have got an answer to the two prior ones,—What is the nature of the intuitions ? and what the precise object looked at ?—questions which will be settled as we examine the intuitions in order. The question as to what saith the intuition, is not the same as the question as to whether the intuition should be trusted. It is expedient to de- termine precisely what the witness says, before we inquire whether he does or does not speak the truth; and so we adjourn this last question to the close of our survey. In questioning the witness, it will be necessary, when a testimony is given in favour of a reality independent 88 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. of the contemplative mind, to determine very precisely what is the sort of reality. In particular the question should be put, Is the attestation in behalf of an inde- pendent thing, or merely of the quality of a thing, or of the relation between one thing and another, or what else ? For example, self-consciousness seems to testify in behalf of self as an individual existence, and sense-perception seems to assert of bodily objects that they have a sepa- rate being; but when the mind contemplates thinking, or solidity, or potency, though it undoubtedly affirms of them that they are real, it does not look on them as se- parate entities, as this paper or as this book is. The mind declares that moral excellence is a reality, and not a figment; but it does not attribute the same sort of reality to it as it does to the man who possesses moral excellence. The mind seems to me to declare that there is a reality in space and time, but we may land ourselves in innumerable difficulties if we make rash assertions as to the kind of reality we give them. Unless we draw such distinctions, we may altogether misunderstand the testimony given, and then be tempted to charge the blunders, which our own hastiness has committed, on our mental constitution. And yet these are distinctions which are altogether lost sight of by those who juggle with the phrases ‘objective’ and ‘subjective.’ Even in our most sub- jective exercises, as when the mind is thinking of one of its own states, there is always an object known, namely, self; and when we say that such a thing has an objec- tive existence, we may mean a great many different things which should be carefully distinguished.* The meaning and importance of these cautions may best be comprehended by giving examples of the evil which has arisen from neglecting them. Kant laboured * On Subjective and Objective, see Part III. Book I. Chap. II. sect, v., Supplementary. METHOD OE APPLICATION. 89 to determine more critically than had been done before, the nature of the mind’s convictions regarding space, time, and causation, and he stood up resolutely for their reality; but then it was a merely subjective reality—a reality in the mind. Time and space are represented by him as forms under which we cognize all phenomena presented to the senses, and cause and effect is a cate- gory under which events are arranged by the under- standing. Now, in examining this theory, I start with inquiring, What do our native convictions say in regard to these subjects ? Are they satisfied when it is said that time and space and causation have no existence out of the mind? They seem to me, on the contrary, to declare that time and space have a reality out of the mind, and independent of the mind, quite as much as the phenomena which we discover in space and time, and that cause and effect have an existence quite as much as the events which they connect. No doubt I may deny the trustworthiness of my intuitive convictions as attesting the existence of external being, but immedi- ately after, some one, proceeding a step further in the same direction, will deny the trustworthiness of all their other testimonies, till we are landed in a scepticism which sets aside the reality, subjective as well as ob- jective. This is an illustration of evil arising from a refusal to listen to our convictions. Mistakes have also arisen from neglecting the distinctions between the kinds of testi- mony. M. Cousin finds fault, very properly, with Kant, for not allowing an objective existence to substance and causation, and other truths attested by reason. But then lie does not institute a patient inquiry into the nature of the reality which the mind gives to such things as sub- stance and cause and moral good; and he argues as if these must have the same sort of reality as the individual 90 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. soul has, or as an individual acting causally has, or as a good man has; and he has thus been led to argue at once, from our idea of objective substance to God as absolute substance, from creature effect to God as the Supreme Cause, and from the idea of moral good to the existence of a good God,—a mode of argument which I cannot but regard as inconclusive and highly unsatisfac- tory, the more so as it operates, with other considera- tions, to lead him to represent God as a cause which must create.* By steadily adhering to this method of induction, and attending to such cautions, we may surely hope to be able to ascertain something as to the original principles of the mind, and determine likewise what are the truths guaranteed by them: and this, I apprehend, is the main work which metaphysics should attempt. In regard to systems not built upon inductive psycho- logical proof, I confess that to me they are all very much alike; they differ only in respect of the intellectual tem- perament of the individual constructing them, or the influences under which he has been nurtured. The man of genius, like Schelling, will create an ingenious theory, beautiful as the golden locks of the setting sun ; the man of vigorous intellect, like Hegel, will erect a fabric which looks as coherent as a palace of ice: but until they can * See a summary of liis admirable review of Kant, Prem. Ser. tom. v. Ie9. viii. In Prem. Ser. tom. ii. Ie9- vii., viii., xiv., xxii., he labours to show that the ideas of the true, the beautiful, the good, imply the existence of a God who is the true, the beautiful, the good; and in Deux. Ser. tom. i. Ie9. iv., v., that the finite implies the infinite, that the effect implies a cause, and the cause an effect. In these last lectures he had spoken of God as necessarily creating. In Fragments Philoso- pliiques, Aver, de la trois. ed., he withdraws the language ‘ necessity of creation,’ as not sufficiently reverent towards the Creator; but he ad- heres to the meaning, “ Or en Dieu surtout la force est adequate a la substance, et la force divine est toujours en acte ; Dieu est done cssen- tiellement actif et createur.” METHOD OF APPLICATION. 91 be shown to be founded on the inherent principles of the mind, or to be built up of materials thence derived, I wrap myself up in philosophic doubt, as not being sure whether they may disappear while I am gazing on them. Nor am I to be seduced into an admiration of such imposing systems by the plea often urged in their behalf, that they furnish a gymnasium for the exercise of the intellect. I acknowledge that one of the very highest ad- vantages of study of every description is to be found in the vigour imparted to the mind which pursues it. But whatever may have been the difficulty in the days of the schoolmen, it is not necessary now to resort to fruitless a priori speculation, in order to find an arena in which to exercise the intellect. Nay, I am convinced that when the research conducts to no solid results, it will weary the mind without strengthening it; the effort will be like that of one who beateth the air, and activity will always be followed by exhaustion, by dissatisfaction, and an un- willingness to make further exertion. Labour, it is true, is its own reward; but if there be no other reward, there will be the want of the needful incentive. The vigour im- parted is only one of the incidental effects which follow when labour is undertaken in the hope of securing substan- tial fruits. Nor is it to be forgotten that these speculations, though fruitless of good, are not fruitless of evil. In the struggles thus engendered there are other powers of the mind tried as well as the understanding; there are often sad agonizings of the feelings, of the faith, and indeed of the whole soul, which feels as if the foundation on which it previously stood had been removed and none other supplied, and as if it had in consequence to sink for ever ; or as if it were doomed to move for ever onward without reaching a termination, while all retreat has been cut off behind. In these wrestlings I fear that many wounds are inflicted, which continue long to rankle and 92 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. often terminate in something worse than the dissolution of the bodily organism, for they end in the loss of faith and of peace, in cases in which they do not issue in im- morality, in scepticism, or in blasphemy. Any sentiment of admiration which might be excited by the display of mental power and learning on the part of the speculators, is counteracted in my mind by more painful associations than the Quaker poet connected with the sound of the drum. “ I hate that drum’s discordant sound, Parading round and round and round; To me it talks of ravaged plains, And burning towns and ruined swains, And mangled limbs and dying groans, And widows’ tears and orphans’ moans, And all that Misery’s hand bestows To fill the catalogue of human woes.” These exercises, I suspect, resemble not so much those of the gymnasium, as of the ancient gladiatorial shows, in which no doubt there were many brilliant feats per- formed, but in which also members were mutilated, and the heart’s-blood of many a brave man shed. I fear that in not a few cases generous and courageous youths have entered the lists, to lose in the contest all creed, all re- ligious, and in some cases, all moral principle, and with these all peace and all stability. “ I see before me the gladiator lie, He leans upon his hand—his manly brow Consents to death, but conquers agony ; And his drooped head sinks gradually low: And through his side the last drops ebbing slow From the big gash, fall heavy one by one, Like the first of a thunder-shower. And now The arena swims around him—he is gone.” Sect. Y. What Explanation can be given of the Intuitions of the Mind ? As we are about forthwith to ask the Intuitions to METHOD OF APPLICATION. 93 give an account of themselves, it may be as well to have it settled what sort of information we may expect to draw from them. Our intuitions are at once the clearest and the dark- est objects which the mind can contemplate; constituting the intellectual sense by which we get all our original knowledge, it is found to be a painful and arduous work to turn back the eye upon itself. Truths seen by intui- tion shine in their own light, like the luminary of day, and any attempt to make them clearer is like “ going out with a taper to see the sun,” and yet when we would look steadily on them our eye is apt to be blenched. In another respect too they are like the sun—they shine the brightest when we get the first glance at them, and if we continue to gaze, they appear dim and dark to our op- pressed vision. And yet it is only by reflexly looking on them as they shine, that we can expect to be able to de- termine their form and dimensions. There are senses in which they cannot, there are senses in which they can be explained. I. 1. They cannot be explained in the sense of being rendered intelligible to any one naturally without them. He who is born blind cannot be made to see colours by help of a microscope or telescope, nor could the most vivid description give him any idea of them. In like manner, if there were a human being without the intui- tions, he could not be made to understand the objects which they reveal: he who does not see them when he opens his eyes, will never be enabled to behold them by any logical process of explanation or definition. If men were without the native capacity of perceiving extension, or power of discerning moral good, it would be impossi- ble by any description or argument to convey the dim- mest idea of them. This is one reason why the subject of our original perceptions has been felt to be so very 94 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. mysterious. It is seen that human discussion can do nothing in clearing them up, and that if it attempt to do so, it is only “ darkening counsel by words without knowledge.” But all this dazzling of our eye arises not from any darkness enveloping them, but from the very brightness of the light in which they shine. 2. They cannot be explained in the sense of being re- solved into simpler elements. In physical science we can gain important information regarding many objects, by resolving them into their constituents ; even there however we come to simple substances which cannot be decomposed. In mental science we can explain many phenomena by explicating the processes involved in the formation of them ; thus, in regard to the perception of distance by the eye, we can show what are the original endowments of the sense of sight, and what are the ac- quisitions of experience ; and in regard to reasoning, we can point out the relation of premisses and conclusion. But in the process of decomposition we must come to simple properties which admit of no analysis. The in- tuitive principles of the mind are the simple powers to which we owe all our original cognitions : he who would attempt to cut these atoms will find the edge of his ana- lysis bent back and blunted, as the razor is when it is applied to the rock. d. They cannot be explained in the sense of being re- ferred to higher principles from which they derive their authority. Some phenomena, both material and mental, can be thus shown to hang on higher truths: the move- ments of the planets and of the moon up in the sky, are dependent on the law of gravitation, and on the colloca- tion of the several bodies. We may lawfully and pro- fitably seek out for the authority on which certain of our apprehensions or cognitions rest: we may trace the steps, for example, by which we are led to believe that Julius METHOD OF APPLICATION. 95 Caesar lived, or that Jesus Christ died and rose again, or those by which we come to be assured that the square of the hypothenuse of a right-angled triangle is equal to the square of the other two sides. But in all such regres- sions we must at last come back to something original, and having its authority in itself. For some things we must have a foundation, but we do not seek for a foundation for everything. It wTas the idea that everything must lean on something else, which led the Indians to place the earth on the back of an ele- phant, and to make the elephant stand on a tortoise. I use this as a mere illustration. It is quite true that most truths known to us stand on other truths. But we come at last to truths which stand on nothing else. The mind does not feel on this account that the truths are less stable: it is convinced as to certain truths that they need something else to lean on ; but of certain truths it sees that they bear up other truths and yet themselves need no support beyond or beneath them; and it sees that these are the truths which are the firmest and the most secure. He who would go beyond them is going further back than the beginning; he who would go fur- ther down is trying to get beneath the foundation. II. But there are senses in which an account or an explanation can be given of them. 1. Negative definitions may be given of them. The knowledge which we have of the objects being in its very nature the simplest of all knowledge, we cannot make it simpler. But if any one mistakes in regard to the objects, and says that they possess qualities which we know do not belong them, then we can correct him. We can by reason of our intimate knowledge of the objects make an indefinite number of negative assertions regard- ing them. Thus, we can affirm of self perceiving that it is different from the body perceived, of extension that it 96 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. is not the same as consciousness or intelligence, of space and time that they can have no bounds, of moral excel- lence that it is not the same as the pleasurable, and of vice that it is not the same as the painful. These nega- tive propositions may be made to face error from what- ever quarter it makes its hostile assaults. 2. Their peculiarity may be brought out by abstrac- tion. Not that their nature may be explained to one who is not already cognizant of them. But the native cogni- zance which the mind has of them is concrete, is mixed. Several intuitions are mingled in one act, or our intui- tive perceptions are bound up with our derivative or ex- periential exercises. As long as our reflex knowledge is of this character, it is indistinct and confused, and we are ever liable to fall into error when we make affirma- tions regarding it; for what we assert of the whole, or of every one of the parts, may be true only of some or of one of the parts. But by analysis we can make the given intuitions stand forth separately to the view, just as by experiment in physical science we can separate the agencies of nature which usually work in combina- tion,—separate, for example, in the exhausted receiver of an air-pump, the power which draws a body to the earth from the resistance given to it in ordinary circumstances by the atmosphere. Looking at it thus, we can distin- guish and express its peculiarity. Not that this expres- sion could convey any meaning to one without the intui- tion, but to one with the intuition the meaning flashes immediately on the vision. Naturally, there is never a knowledge of not-self without a co-existing knowledge of self, but by abstraction we can separate the two and look at each by itself; and when we describe the not- self as extended or in motion, or the self as conscious and intelligent, an apprehension at once starts up in the mind corresponding to the object. METHOD OP APPLICATION. 97 3. The nature of the object intuitively known can be specified. Not indeed that it could be apprehended by one Avithout the proper perception, but to one with the corresponding intuition its nature can be distinctly stated. Thus we can, in intelligent language, describe the ex- tension of body as its being contained in space and oc- cupying space, and virtue as the approvable quality of voluntary actions ol intelligent beings, and the mind at once understands what is meant to be affirmed of the objects. 4. We may generalize or classify the intuitions of the mind.* Fixing by abstraction on certain common qualities, we may then, by generalization, place all those possessing them into one class. We may fix on the more marked and decided points of resemblance, with their implied differences, and this will give us the Grand Divisions. We may then divide and subdivide, accord- ing to other, and minor, but still important points of resemblance and difference, in due ordination and subor- dination. In this Treatise we classify the intuitions ac- cording to what they look at and discover, as I. The True. II. The Good. I. The True. 1. Primitive Cognitions. 2. Primitive Beliefs. 3. Primitive Judgments. The justification of this arrangement can be found only in its embracing all the phenomena, and of this the reader must judge as we proceed with the exposition. I speak of our intuitions as looking to the true and the good, and the true and the good thus perceived have a reality, but this is not to be understood as a reality of the same sort as is possessed by individual things, which * Locke says truly, that if we include all self-evident propositions, principles will be almost infinite (Essay, book ii. cb. vii. s. 10). Hence the need of generalizing them. as CHARACTER OP INTUITIONS. may be true or good. They have a reality, not as indi- vidual entities, but as common qualities, which should be expressed by a common epithet. But the qualities always imply individual objects, in which they inhere. And wherever the qualities of knowledge and moral excellence are to be found in the creature they are but emanations from the Creator. The streams, if we follow them, will lead us up to the Fountain. It will be seen that our intuitive convictions, whether they relate to the true or the good, all conduct us to Him who is emphati- cally the True and the Good. CHAPTER III. (SUPPLEMENTARY.) BEIEF CEITICAL REVIEW OF OPINIONS IN REGARD TO INTUITIVE TRUTHS. I. The Pee-Soceatic Schools oe Geeece.—The Greek phi- losophers who flourished in the sixth and fifth centuries before Christ, if they did not exactly discuss, did, at least, start the ques- tion of man’s native power of intuition. The Ionian School, founded by Thales, and continued by Anaximander, Anaximenes, Anaxago- ras, and others, dwelling among material elements, found only the mutable and the fleeting; till at length it was laid down systema- tically by Heraclitus, that all things were in a state of perpetual flux, under the power of an ever-kindling and ever-extinguishing fire., Eunning to the opposite extreme, the Eleatic School, of which Xenophanes, Parmenides, and Zeno were the most illus- trious masters, appealed altogether from sense and opinion (Sofa) to reason (Aoyos) ; fixed its attention on the abiding nature of things beneath all mutation; dived into profound, but over-subtle, and often confused and quibbling disquisitions re- garding Being; and ended by making all things so fixed that change and motion became impossible. It was in the very midst of the collision of these sects that Socrates was reared. Pro- fessing to have only a practical aim in view, he yet, in putting CRITICAL REVIEW OF OPINIONS. 99 down the opposition to that end, indulged in all the subtlety of a Greek intellect, and thus stimulated the dialectic spirit of his pupil Plato, who sought to harmonize the fleeting and the fixed. II. Plato.—It would be altogether a mistake to suppose, as some have done, that Plato is for ever inquiring into the origin of ideas in the mind, like the metaphysicians who came after Des- cartes and Locke. His aim was of a character loftier and wider, but more unattainable by the cogitation of one thinker, or indeed by cogitation at all. Nor was it his object to discover the abso- lute, as if he had been reared in the schools of Schilling or Hegel. His grand aim was to discover the real (to ov) and the abiding, amidst the illusions of sense and the mutations of things. And in following this end he sought prematurely to determine questions which can be settled only by a long course of patient induction, carried on by a succession of observers of the world without and the world within. But in the search he started many deep views of God, of man, and of the world, which have been established by the Bible, aud by inductive mental and physical science. 1. He everywhere proceeds on the doctrine that man is possessed of a power of reason (Adyo?, or roCs, or vorjcns) above sense, or faith, or understanding (Sidvoia). 2. This reason contemplates ideas (iS«u, or €i8rf) suprasensible, immutable, eternal, which ideas are realities. 3. He sees that there is need of a process of thought, specially of abstraction, in order to the mind rising to these ideas. 4. The discovery of these ideas should be the especial aim of the philosopher, and the gazing on them the highest exercise of wis- dom. But Plato moves above our earth like the sun, with so dazzling a light that we feel unable, or unwilling, to look too nar- rowly into the exact body of truth which sheds such a lustre. 1. He has given a wrong account of the reality in these eternal ideas, making them the only realities; denying reality to the ob- jects of sense, except in so far as they partake of them, and seem- ing to make them independent even of the Divine Mind. 2. Under the one phase, ‘idea,’ he gathers an aggregate of things which require to be distinguished,—such as the true, the beautiful, the good, unity and being, natural law and moral law, the forms of objects, and even the universals fashioned arbitrarily by the mind. By heaping together and confounding all these things which should be carefully distinguished, he has given a grandeur to his views, but at the expense of clearness and accuracy. 3. He does not see that ideas exist naturally in the mind merely in the form of laws or rules. To account for them he is obliged to suppose that the soul pre-existed, and that the calling up of the ideas is a 100 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. sort of reminiscence. 4. He does not see how the mind reaches them in their abstract, general, or philosophic form. He did not observe that the mind begins with the knowledge of particular objects, and must thence rise by induction to generals. He thus laid himself open to the assaults, always acute, often just, at times captious, of Aristotle, who saw that the general existed in the individuals, and that it was from the singulars that man rose to the universals (see Metaph. i. 12.) 5. He attaches an ex- travagant value to the contemplation of these ideas in their abstract and general form. Overlooking the other purposes served by ideas, and their indissoluble connection with singulars,—forgetting that philosophy consists in viewing law in relation to its objects,— he represents the mind as in its highest exercise when it is gazing upon them in their essence, formless and colourless: 'H yap dypw/ca- ros T6 /cat <\o")(qfL(LTL(TTOp6vr](Ti<;, nor nor €7710-7777*77, but voCs, which has to do with the principles of science: Aewrerat vovv elmt twu apyaii/ (Eth. Nic. vi. 6 : ed. Michelet). 2. He fixes on self-evidence and independence as tests of what he calls first truths and prin- ciples. First truths are those whose credit is not through others, but of themselves. *Evcm fiev ovv irporepog kuI yvwpip-wrepog o bid rov fiecrov s av Set TavTas viroXafidiv ov paStov ewreij/. For this statement he gives reasons, which lead him to the conclusion that the universals which are predicated of individuals are princi- ples in the ratio of their universality, and that the very highest generalizations must be emphatically principles : Trp/ p.lv yap dpxqv 8el /cat Tyjv air Lav etvat 7rapa to. 7rpayp,ara wv d.pyr}, /cat SvvcurOai etvat XWpLt,Opievr)V aVTWV TOLOVTOV 84 TL 7rapd TO KaO' CKaLTTOV CLVCLL 8La TL dv rt? v7roXdj3oL, 7r\rjv on KaOoXov KarqyopeLTaL /cat Kara 7ravrwv; dXXd pLTjv, et 8La tovto, to. pdXXov KaOoXov p.d\\ov OtTeov wcttc dpyat ra rrpwT dv dhqaav yevr] (ii. 3. 15). There are points of connection not brought out in this statement. But we are not rashly to charge Aristotle with an inconsistency. I believe that his statement as to first truths and syllogism, and his state- ment as to the universality of induction, are both true. But he has not drawn the distinction between first principles as forms in the mind, and as individual convictions, and as laws got by in- duction ; nor has he seen how the self-evidence and necessity, being in the singulars, goes up into the universals when (but only when) the induction is properly formed. IV. Descartes seized on a large body of important truth in regard to innate ideas. 1. Tie saw that they were of the nature of powers or faculties ready to operate, but needing to be called forth. “ Lorsque je dis que quelque idee est nee avec nous, ou qu’elle est naturellement empreinte en nos arnes, je n’entends pas qu’elle se presente toujours a notre pensee, car ainsi il n’y en aurait aucune ; mais j’entends seulement que nous avons en nous- memes la faculte de la produire ” (Trois Objec. Bep. Obj. 10). See other passages to the same effect, quoted by Mr. AVitch, Trans, of Med., etc., pp. 207-208. 2. He had a glimpse, but confused, of the test of self-evidence, which he unhappily represents as clear- ness. “ Toutes les choses que nous concevons clairement et dis- tinctement sont vraies de la faqon dont nous les concevons ” (Med. Abrege). He thus explains clearness and distinctness: “J’ap- CRITICAL REVIEW OE OPINIONS. 103 pelle claire celle qui est presente et manifeste a un esprit attentif; de meme que nous disons voir clairement les objets, lorsqu’etant presents a nos yeux ils agissent assez fort sur eux, et qu’ils sont disposes a les regarder; et distincte, celle qui est tellement precise et differente de toutes les autres, qu’elle ne comprend en soi que ce qui paroit nianifestement a celui qui la considere coniine il faut” (Prin. Phil. i. 45). 3. He sees that they assume the shape of common notions. 4. These are represented as eternal truths of intelligence. “ Lorsque nous pensons 'qu’ou ne sauroit laire quelque chose de rien, nous ne croyons point que cette proposition soit une chose qui existe ou la propriete de quelque chose, mais nous la prenons pour une certaine verite eternelle qui a son siege en notre pensee, et que l’on nomme une notion commune ou une rnaxime ; tout de meme quand on dit qu’il est impossible qu’une meme chose soit et ne soit pas en meme temps, que ce qui a ete fait ne peut n’etre pas fait, que celui qui pense ne peut manquer d’etre ou d’exister pendant qu’il pense, et quantite d’autres sem- blables, ce sont seulement des verites, et non pas des choses qui soient hors de notre pensee, et il y en a un si grand nombre de telles qu’il seroit malaise de les denombrer” (Prin. Phil. i. 49). 5. He discovers that they come forth into consciousness; hence he calls them innate ideas, and defines idea: “ Cette forme de chacune de nos pensees par la perception immediate de laquelle nous avons connaissance de ces memes pensees” (Rep. aux Deux Object.). But there is confusion throughout, in the view which he takes and in his mode of expression. 1. He gives no account of the relation between the faculty on the one hand, and the idea or common notion on the other. He does not see that abstraction and gene- ralization are necessary in order to reach the abstract and general idea. 2. The test of self-evidence is not well expressed; in this respect he is inferior to Locke. The clearness and distinctness of an idea is, to say the least of it, a very ambiguous phrase, for in some senses of the word we may have a very clear idea of an ima- ginary object, or a distinct idea of a falsehood. 3. That there is confusion in his view is evident from the circumstance that he often states that these truths are not equally admitted by all, be- cause they are opposed to the prejudices of some. He speaks of persons “ qui ont imprime de longue main des opinions en leur creance, qui etaient contraires a quelques-unes de ces verites ” (Prin. i. 50). 4. He expects far too much from a bare contem- plation of the principles or causes of things. “ Mais l’ordre que j’ai tenu en ceci a ete tel: premierement, j’ai tache de trouver en general les principes ou premieres causes de tout ce qui est ou 104 CHARACTER OE INTUITIONS. qui peut etre dans le monde, sans rien considerer pour cet efiet que Dieu seul qui l’a cree, ni les tirer d’ailleurs que de certaines semences de verites qui sont naturellement en nos ames. Apres cela, j’ai examine quels etaient les premiers et les plus ordinaires effefcs qu’on pouvait deduire de ces causes; et il me semble que par la j’ai trouve des cieux, des astres, une terre, et meme sur la terre de 1’eau, de l’air, etc.” (Meth. P. vi.). Y. Locke has, in his account of the Human Understanding, both a sensational or rather an experiential element, and a rational element. Eagerly bent on establishing his favourite position that all our ideas are derived from sensation and reflection, he has not blended these elements very successfully, nor been at much pains to show their consistency. In Prance they took the sensational element, and overlooked the other. The Arians and Socinians ot Britain seized eagerly on the rational element. In his unmeasured condemnation of innate ideas in the Pirst Book of his Essay, he seems to deny truths which he openly defends or incidentally allows in other parts of the work. 1. He gives a high place to reason. Thus, in replying to Stilliugfleet, he says:—“Reason, as standing for true and clear principles, and also as standing for clear and fair deductions from those principles, I have not wholly omitted; as is manifest from what I have said of self-evident pro- positions, intuitive knowledge, and demonstration, in other parts of my Essay.” Speaking of self-evident propositions :—“ Whe- ther they come in view of the mind earlier or later, this is true of them, that they are all known by their native evidence, are wholly independent, receive no light, nor are capable ol any proof one from another ” (see Rogers’s Essays, Locke, p. 47). 2. He gives an important place to intuition. 3. He fixes on self-evi- dence as the mark of intuition. “ Sometimes the mind perceives the agreement or disagreement of two ideas immediately by them- selves, without the intervention of any other; and this I think we may call intuitive knowledge. Prom this the mind is at no pains of proving or examining, but perceives the truth, as the eye doth light, only by being directed towards it.” “This kind of know- ledge is the clearest and most certain that human frailty is capable of. This part of knowledge is irresistible, and, like bright sunshine, forces itself immediately to be perceived as soon as ever the mind turns its view that way, and leaves no room for hesitation, doubt, or examination, but the mind is presently filled with the clear light of it.” “ He that demands a greater certainty than this, demands he knows not what, and shows only that he has a mind to be a sceptic without being able to be so” (Essay, bk. iv. ch. CRITICAL REVIEW OE OPINIONS. 105 ii. sect. 1; see also book iv. chap. xvii. sect. 4). Among truths known intuitively, “ we have an intuitive knowledge of our own existence ” (bk. iv. ch. iii. sect. 21) ; and “ man knowrs by an intuitive certainty that bare nothing can no more produce any real Being than it can be equal to two right-angles ” (bk. iv. ch. x. sect. 3). 4. He is obliged at times to appeal to necessity of conception. Thus, in arguing with Stillingfleet:—“ The idea of beginning to be, is necessarily connected with the idea of some operation ; and the idea of operation with the idea of something operating, which we call a cause.” “ The idea of a right-angled triangle necessarily carries with it an equality of its angles to two right ones; nor can we conceive this relation, this connection of these two ideas, to be possibly mutable ” (Essay, bk. iv. ch. iii. sect. 29). He speaks of certain and universal knowledge as having “necessary connection,” “ necessary co-existence,” “necessary de- pendence” (see Webb on the Intellectualism of Locke, P. iii.) 5. He sees that intuitive general maxims are all derived from particulars. This follows from his general maxim that the mind begins with particulars. “ The ideas first in the mind, ’tis evident, are those of particular things, from which by slow degrees the understanding proceeds to some few general ones ” (bk. iv. ch. vii. sect. 9). “In particulars our knowledge begins, and so spreads itself by degrees to generals” (bk. iv. ch. vii. sect. 11). Follow- ing out this view, he speaks of the general propositions being “ not innate but collected from a preceding acquaintance and re- flection on particular instances. These wdien observing men have made them, unobserving men when they are proposed to them cannot refuse their assent to” (bk. i. ch. ii. sect. 21). G. He saw clearly—what Kant never saw—that the mind rises to uni- versal propositions by looking at things, and the nature of things. “ Had they examined the ways whereby men come to the know- ledge of many universal truths, they would have found them to result in the minds of men from the being of things themselves when duly considered, and that they were discovered by the appli- cation of those faculties which were fitted by nature to receive and judge of them when duly employed about them (bk. i. ch. iv. sect. 25). But, on the other hand, Locke has omitted or controverted cer- tain great truths. 1. He imagines that when he has disproved innate ideas in the sense of phantasms, and general notions, he has therefore disproved them in every sense. 2. He does not see that the intuition which he acknowledges, must have a rule, law, or principle, which may be described as innate, inasmuch as it is in 106 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. the mind prior to all experience. 3. Misled by his theory of the mind looking at ideas and not at things, he represents intui- tion as concerned solely with the comparison of ideas. This was noticed by the Bishop of , in a letter dated Johns- toun, October 2G, 1G97, to Locke’s friend, Mr. Molyneux:—“ To me it seems that, according to Mr. Locke, I cannot be said to know anything except there be two ideas in my mind, and all the knowledge I have must be concerning the relation these two ideas have to one another, and that I can be certain of nothing else, which in my opinion excludes all certainty of sense and of single ideas, all certainty of consciousness, such as willing, con- ceiving, believing, knowing, etc., and, as he confesses, all certainty of faith, and, lastly, all certainty of remembrance of which I have formerly demonstrated as soon as I have forgot or do not actually think of the demonstration” (Letters between Locke and Moly- neux). Reid refers to Locke’s notion that belief or knowledge consists in a perception of the agreement or disagreement of ideas, and characterizes it “ as one of the main pillars of modern scepticism.” “I say a sensation exists, and I think I under- stand clearly what I mean. But you want to make the thing clearei’, and for that end tell me that there is an agreement be- tween the idea of that sensation and the idea of existence. To speak freely, this conveys to me no light, but darkness. I can conceive no otherwise of it than as an odd and obscure circumlo- cution. I conclude then that the belief which, accompanies sensa- tion and memory is a simple act of the mind which cannot be defined” (Works, p. 107). 4. He does not see the peculiar nature of intuitive maxims. He perceives that they are got by general- ization—the great truth overlooked by the special supporters of innate ideas; but he fails to observe that they are the general- ization of primitive cognitions and truths, which cany with them self-evidence and necessity. VL Leibnitz had profound but, in some respects, extravagant views of necessary truths. 1. He sees that they have a place in the mind, as habitudes, dispositions, aptitudes, faculties. “ Les connaissances ou les verites, en tant qu’elles sont en nous, quand meme on n’y pense point, sont des habitudes ou des dispositions ” (Nouv. Essais, Opera, p. 213: ed. Erdmann). At the same place he calls them * aptitudes.' “ Lorsqu’on dit que les notions innees sont implicitement dans l’esprit, cela doit signifier seulement, qu’il a la faculte de les connaitre” (p. 212). 2. “Leibnitz has the honour of first explicitly enouncing the criterion of necessity, and Kant of first fully applying it to the phenomena. In nothing CRITICAL REVIEW OF OPINIONS. 107 has Kant been more successful than in this under consideration.” So says Hamilton (Eeid’s Works, p. 323). The remark seems cor- rect ; hut it should be added that Aristotle, as has been shown, ex- pressly fixed on necessity, while others appealed to it; even Locke speaks of knowledge as “ irresistible,” and of “necessary relations.” Leibnitz draws more decidedly than had been done before, the distinction between necessary and eternal truths and truths of experience (p. 209). 3. Because of the natural faculty and “ pre- formation,” the ideas tend to come into consciousness in a special form. “ II y a toujours une disposition particuliere a Taction, et a une action plutot qu’a Tautre ” (p. 223). He illustrates this by supposing that in the marble there might be veins which marked out a particular figure, say that of Hercules preferably to others. “ Mais s’il y avoit des veines dans la pierre, qui marquassent la figure d’Hercule preferablement a d’autres figures, cette pierre y seroit plus determinee, et Hercule y seroit comme inne en quelque (p. 196). 4. He represents the intellect itself as a source of ideas. To the maxim “ Niliil est in intellectu quod non fuerit in sensu,” he adds, “ nisi ipse intellectus.” The expression is not very explicit. He explains it:—“ Or Tame renferme l’etre, la sub- stance, Tun, le meme, la cause, la perception, le raisonnement, et quantite d’autres notions.” But he is surely wrong in identifying these with Locke’s ideas of reflection (p. 223). 5. He sees that there is need of more than spontaneity, that there is need of some intellectual process, in order to discover the general truth. “ Les maximes innees ne paroissent que par l’attention qu’on leur donne ” (p. 213). But,—1. He separates necessary truth from things, and making them altogether mental, he led the way to that subjective tendency which was carried so far by Kant. 2. He does not distinguish between the necessary principle as a disposi- tion unconsciously in the mind, and a general maxim discovered by a process. 3. He does not see that the general maxim is reached by generalizing the individual necessary truths. VII. Buffier’s principal treatise is on ‘ Premieres Verites.’ He saw:—1. That there was in the mind an original law, which he characterizes as a 1 disposition.’ 2. He speaks of it as coming forth in common and uniform judgments among all men or the greater part. 3. He sees that it does not thus come forth till mature age, and till men come to the use of reason. These three points are all brought out in the following sentence. “ J’entends ici par le Sens Commen, la disposition que la nature a mise dans tous les hommes, ou manifestement dans la plupart d’entre eux, pour leur faire porter, quand ils ont atteint l’usage de la raison, 108 CHARACTER OI INTUITIONS. un jugement commun et uniforme sur des objets differents du sen- timent intime de leur propre perception : jugement qui n’est point la consequence d’aucun principe anterieur” (p. i. c. v.). 4. He specifies several important practical characteristics of first truths. “ (1.) Le premier de ces caracteres est qu’elles soient si claires, que quand on entreprend de les prouver ou de les attaquer, on ne le puisse faire que par des propositions qui manifestement ne sont ni plus claires ni plus certaines. (2.) D’etre si universellement re- 9ues parmi les homines en tout temps, en tous lieux, et par toutes sortes d’esprits, que ceux qui les attaquent se trouvent, dans le genre humain, etre manifestement moins d’un centre cent, ou meme contremille. (3.) D’etre si fortement imprimees dans nous, que nous y conformions notre conduite, malgre les raffinements de ceux qui imaginent des opinions contraires, et qui eux-memes agissent conformement, non a leurs opinions imaginees, mais aux premieres verites universellement (p. i. c. vii.). It does not appear however that (1) he fixed explicitly on their deeper qualities of self-evidence and necessity, nor (2) showed the rela- tion between their individual and general form. VII. Reid’s great merit lies in establishing certain principles of Common Sense, such as those of substance and quality, cause and effect, and moral good, as against the scepticism of Hume. He does not profess to give an exhaustive account of these prin- ciples, nor to enter minutely into their distinctive character and mode of operation, but in conducting his proper work, he has mentioned nearly all their distinctive qualities. 1. He represents them as being in the nature of man: thus he speaks of “ an origi- nal principle of our constitution” (p. 121), and calls them “original and natural judgments,” as “part of that furniture which Nature hath given to the human understanding,” as “ the inspiration of the Almighty” and “a part of our constitution ” (p. 209, Works : Hamilton’s edition). 2. He represents the mind as having a sense or perception of them; and on the one hand avoids the error of Locke, who regards intuition as concerned solely with a comparison of ideas, and he does not on the other hand fall into that of Kant, who looks on them as mere forms in the mind. 3. He follows Locke in fixing on self-evidence as a decisive test. “ We ascribe to reason two offices, or two degrees. The first is to judge of things self-evident; the second, to draw conclusions that are not self-evident from those that are. The first of these is the province, and the sole province, of common sense, and there- fore it coincides with reason in its whole extent, and is only an- other name for one branch or one degree of reason ” (p. 425 : see CRITICAL REVIEW OF OPINIONS 109 also p. 422). 4. He specifics necessity as a mark. “ By the con- stitution of our nature we are under a necessity of assent to them” (p. 130). He speaks of a certain truth u being a necessary truth, and therefore no object of sense.” “ It is not that things which begin to exist commonly have a cause, or even that they al- ways in fact have a cause, but that they must have a cause and cannot begin to exist without a cause” (p. 455: see also pp. 521, 456). Yet he has not a steady apprehension of necessity as a test, for he says:—“ I resolve for my own part always to pay a great regard to the dictates of common sense, and not to depart from them without absolute necessity” (p. 113), as if necessity did not preclude our departing from them. 5. He characterizes them as universal; thus he appeals to the “ universal consent of mankind ; not of philosophers only, but of the rude and unlearned vulgar” (p. 456). His positive errors on this subject are not many, but he has not seen the full truth, and he has fallen into several oversights. 1. By neglecting a rigid use of tests, he has described some truths as first principles, into which there enters an experiential element. Thus, for example, “ that there is life and intelligence in our fellow- men,” “that certain features of the countenance, sounds of the voice, and gestures of the body, indicate certain thoughts and dis- positions of the mind” (p. 448), and that “there is a certain re- gard due to human testimony in matters of fact, and even to hu- man authority in matters of opinion” (450) ; and “that in the phenomena of Nature, what is to be will probably be like to what has been in similar circumstances” (451). A rigid application of the tests of self-evidence and necessity, would have shown that these were not first principles. 2. He is not careful to distin- guish between the Spontaneous and Reflex use of common sense. He uses legitimately the argument from common sense against Hume, but in philosophy we must use the reflex principle care- fully expressed, whereas Reid often appeals in a loose way to the spontaneous conviction. And here I may take the opportunity of stating my conviction (and this notwithstanding Sir W. Hamilton’s defence of it in Note A) that the phrase ‘ common-sense ’ is an unfortunate, because a loose and ambiguous one. Common sense (besides its use by Aristotle, see Hamilton’s Note A) has two meanings in ordinary discourse. It may signify, first, that unac- quired, unbought, untaught sagacity, which certain men have by nature, and which other men never could acquire, even though they were subjected to the process mentioned by Solomon (Prov. xxvii. 22), and brayed in a mortar. Or it may signify the commu- 110 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. nis sensus, or the perceptions and judgments which are common to all men. It is only in this latter sense that the argument from common sense is a philosophic one ; that is, only on the condition that the appeal be to convictions which are in all men ; and fur- ther, that there has been a systematic exposition of them. Keid did make a most legitimate use of the argument from common sense, appealing to convictions in all men, and bringing out to view, and expressing with greater or less accuracy, the principles in- volved in these convictions. But then he has also taken advantage of the first meaning of the phrase; he represents the strength of these original judgments as good sense (p. 209) : he appeals from philosophy to common sense; and in order to counteract the im- pression left by the high intellectual abilities of Hume, he showed that those who opposed Hume were not such fools after all, but had the good sense and shrewdness of mankind on their side (see p. 127, etc., with foot-notes of Hamilton). This has led many to suppose that the argument of Beid and Beattie is alto- gether an address to the vulgar. In this way, what seemed at the time a very dexterous use of a two-edged sword, has turned against those who employed it, and injustice has been done to the Scottish School of philosophers, who do make a proper use of the argument from common sense. 3. He does not see how to recon- cile the doctrine (of Locke) that all maxims appear in conscious- ness as particulars, with his own doctrine of there being principles in the constitution of the mind, and there coming forth in general propositions. IX. Kant has, next to Locke, exercised the greatest influence on modem speculation. As a general rule, the one dwells upon and magnifies the truths which the other overlooks. Kant is a reaction against Locke. He carries out, in his own logical way, certain principles which had grown up in the schools of Descartes, Leibnitz, and "Wolf. 1. He sees more clearly, and explains more fully than ever had been done before, that the a priori principles are in the mind in the character of forms, or rules, prior to their being called forth or exercised. Thus, speaking of our intuition of space, he says it must be ready a priori in the mind, that is, before any perception of objects. “Die Form derselben muss zu ihnen insgesammt im Gemiithe a priori bereit liegen und daher abgesondert von aller Empfindung konnen betrachtet wer- den” (Werke, bd. ii. p. 32 : ed. Kosenkranz). The mind has not only Intuitions of Space and Time to impose on phenomena or presentations, it has Categories of Quantity, Quality, Eolation, Modality, to impose on its cognitions; and Ideas of Substance, CRITICAL REVIEW CE OPINIONS. Ill Totality of Phenomena, and Deity, to impose on the judgments reached by the Categories. 2. He maintains that the forms of the sensibility, and the categories of the understanding, have all a reference to objects of experience, real or possible ; this, in fact, is their use; without this they would be meaningless. The ideas of pure reason do, however, refer to the comparisons of the under- standing, and not to objects, and fruitless speculation arises from supposing that they refer to objects; and there may, also, be an undue use of the forms of sense and the categories of the under- standing, but in themselves they refer to objects of possible ex- perience (Kr. d. r. Yern., Trans. Dial.). 3. He proposes in his great work, the Kritik of Pure Reason, to give an inventory, in systematic order, of the a 'priori principles in the mind. “ Denn es ist nichts als das Inventarium aller unserer Besitze durch reine Yernunft, systematisch geordnet” (Yorrede zu erst. Auf.). He seeks for an organon, which would be a compendium of the principles according to which a priori cognitions would be ob- tained. “Ein Organon der reinen Yernunft wiirde ein Inbegriff derjenigen Principien seyn, nach denen alle reine Erkentnisse a priori konnen erworben und wirklich zu Stande gebracht werden” (Einleit.). 4. He uses systematically the tests of Necessity and Universality, meaning by Universality the Universality of the Truth (see supra, p. 43, foot-note). But, on the other hand, he has fallen into the grossest mis- apprehensions regarding the nature of the a priori principles of reason. 1. He maintains that the mind can have no intuition of things. All that it can know are mere presentations or pheno- mena. It is all true that the Eorms of Sense and the Categories relate to objects of possible experience, but then experience does not give us a knowledge of things. “ Es sind demnach die Gegen- stiinde der Erfahrung niemals an sich selbst.” Speaking even of self-consciousness he says, it does not knowr self as it exists: “ Und selbst ist die innere und sinnliche Anschauung unseres Gemiiths (als Gegenstandes des Bewusstseyns) ... auch nicht das eigentliche Selbst, so wie es an sich existirt” (Bd. ii. p. 389). He thus separates the intuitions of the mind altogether from things. 2. He makes our a priori Intuitions impose on phenomena the forms of Space and Time, wrhich have no existence out of the mind. The categories are frameworks for binding conceptions into judgments. The ideas of pure reason reduce the judgments to unity, but have no re- ference to objects ; and if we suppose them to have, we are landed in illusion and contradictions. By this system he makes much ideal which wre are naturally led to regard as real, and thus pre- 112 CHARACTER OF INTUITIONS. pared the way for Fichte, who made the whole ideal. 3. His Method of discovering the a priori principles of the mind is not the Inductive, but the Critical. Season is called to undertake the task of self-examination, which may secure its righteous claims, not in an arbitrary way, but according to its own eternal and unchangeable laws. “ Eine Aufforderung an die Vernunft, das beschwerlichste aller ihrer Geschafte, namlich das der Selbst- erkenntniss aufs Neue zu ubernehmen und einen Gerichtshof einzusetzen, der sie hei ihren gerechten Anspriichen sichere, da- gegen aber alle grundloseAnmaassungen nicht durchMachtspriiche sondern nach ihren ewigen und unwandelbaren Gesetzen ” (Vor. z. erst. Auf.). Season was thus set on criticizing itself according to laws of its own, and a succession of speculators set out each with what he alleged to be the laws of reason, but no two of them agreed as to what the laws of reason were, or what the standard by which to test them, and conclusions were reached which were evidently most irrational. X. Dugald Stewart delighted to look on our intuitions under the aspect of “ Fundamental Laws of Human Belief” (Elem. vol. ii. ch. i.). 1. He sees that they are of the nature of laws in the mind. 2. He sees that they are natural, original, and fundamental. 3. He sees that they are involved in the facul- ties. Hence he calls them “ elements of reason” (Elem. vol. ii. p. 49: Ham. edit.) ; he would identify them with the exercise of our reasoning powers, and speaks of them as component elements, without which the faculty of reasoning is inconceivable and im- possible (p. 39). It may be added that while he never formally appeals to necessity, he is obliged to use it incidentally. Thus “ every man is impressed with an irresistible conviction that all his sensations, thoughts, and volitions belong to one and the same being” (Elem. vol. i. p. 47); and “we are impressed with an irresistible conviction of our personal identity” (Essays, p. 59). Speaking of causes, in the metaphysical meaning of the word, he says, the “ word cause expresses something which is supposed to he necessarily connected with the change” (Elem. vol. i. p. 97). In looking on them as “ fundamental laws,” and in avoiding the ambiguity of the phrase “ common sense,” he has gone beyond Iteid, but otherwise he has not thrown much light on them. He is in great confusion from not discovering how it is that “ the •elements of reason” may become general maxims, axioms, or prin- ciples. XI. Dr. Thomas Brown has demonstrated, with great in- genuity, that our belief in the invariableness of cause and effect CRITICAL REVIEW OF OPINIONS. 113 cannot be had from experience (Cause and Effect, partiii. sect. 3). He has also shown that the belief in our personal identity is in- tuitive (Lect. 13). When he comes to our intuitions, he speaks of them as “principles of thought;” as “primary universal intui- tions of direct beliefas “ being felt intuitively, universally, imme- diately, irresistiblyas “ an internal, never-ceasing voice from the Creator and Preserver of our being;” as “ omnipotent, like their Author;” and “ such that it is impossible for us to doubt them” (Lect. 13). These are fine expressions, but his view of them is meagre after all, and a retrogression from the Scottish School. He makes no inquiry into their nature, laws, or tests. XXL M. Cousin has given throughout all his philosophical works, clear and beautiful expositions of the elements of reason. 1. It is a favourite doctrine that reason looks at truths, eternal, universal, and absolute; truths, not to the individual or the race, but to all intelligences. 2. He uses, most successfully, the tests of necessity and universality, in order to distinguish the truths of reason from other truths. 3. He has distinguished between the spontaneous and reflective form of the truths of reasons (see supra, p. 62). 4. He has shown that primitive truths are all at first in- dividual. “ C’est un fait qu’il ne faut pas oublier, et qu’on oublie beaucoup trop souvent, que nos jugements sont d’abord des juge- ments particuliers et determines, et que c’est sous cette forme d’un jugementpartieulier et determine que font leur premiere apparition toutes les verites universelles et necessaires ” (ser. ii. t. iii. Ie9.19; see also ser. i. t. i. progr.; t. ii. progr. Ie9- ii.-iv., xi.). But on the other hand, he has given an exaggerated account of the power of human reason, and has not seen that induction is necessary in order to the discovery of necessary truth in its general form. 1. He uses unhappy and unguarded language in speaking of reason. His favourite epithet as applied to it is ‘impersonal;’ language which has a correct meaning inasmuch as the truth is not to the person but to all intelligences, but is often so employed as, with- out his intending it, to come very close to those pantheistic systems which identify the Divine and human reason (see ser. ii. Ie9. v.). 2. His reduction of the ideas of reason to three is full of confusion. The first idea is supposed to be unity, sub- stance, cause, perfect, infinite, eternal; the second, multiple, qua- lity, effect, imperfect, finite, bounded; and the third, the relation of the other two. It is to confound the things which manifestly differ, to make unity, cause, good, infinite indentical. The business of the metaphysician should be to observe each of these carefully, and bring out their peculiarities and their differences. 3. He 114 CHARACTER OP INTUITIONS. does not see how it is that the general maxim is formed out of the particulars. He says that abstraction, “ saisit immediatement ce que le premier objet soumis a son observation renferme de general ” (ser. i. t. i. le£. xi.). He does not see that in order to the formation of the general law there is need of a process, often delicate and laborious, of observation, abstraction, and gene- ralization. XIII. Sib William Hamilton’s Note A, appended to his edition of Eeid’s Works, is the most important contribution made in this century to the science of first truths. 1. He has there specified nearly every important character of our intuitive con- victions, and attached to them an appropriate nomenclature. 2. He has shown that the argument from common sense is one strictly scientific and eminently philosophic. 3. He has with unsurpassed erudition brought testimonies in behalf of the prin- ciples of common sense from the writings of the eminent thinkers of all ages and countries. But on the other hand:—1. He fails to draw the distinction between common sense as an aggregate of laws in the mind, as convictions in consciousness, and as gene- ralized maxims. Thus the confusion of the spontaneous cognition and its generalized form appears in such passages as the follow- ing :—“ The primitive cognitions seem to leap ready from the womb of reason, like Pallas from the head of Jupiter; some- times the mind places them at the commencement of its opera- tions in order to have a point of support and a fixed basis without which the operations would be impossible; sometimes they form in a certain sort the crowning, the consummation of all the intellectual operations” (Metaphysics, Lect. 38). 2. He does not properly appreciate the circumstance that intuitive convictions all look to singulars, and that there is need of induc- tion to reach the general truth. He supposes that the general truth is revealed at once to consciousness. “ Philosophy is the development and application of the constitutive and normal truths which consciousness immediately reveals.” “ Philosophy is thus wrholly dependent on consciousness” (Reid’s Works, p. 746). It is true that philosophy is dependent on consciousness, but it is dependent also on abstraction and generalization. He calls ulti- mate, primary, and universal principles, facts of consciousness (Metaphysics, Lect. 15). 3. His method is not the Inductive, but that of Critical Analysis introduced by Kant (Met. Lect. 29). 4. He fails to observe that the mind in intuition looks at ob- jects. He makes the mind’s conviction in regard to such objects as space, substance, cause, and infinity, to be impotencies, and CRITICAL REVIEW OF OPINIONS. 115 their laws to be laws of thought and not of things (Append, to Discussions on Phil.). The error of such views will come out as we advance. I have endeavoured to expose it in the appendix to ‘Method of Divine Government,’ in an article in the ‘North British Review,’ for August, 1857, and an article in the ‘ Dublin University Magazine,’ for August, 1859. XIV. Dr. Wheweel has done great service at once to the physi- cal sciences and to metaphysics, by showing, in his ‘ Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences,’—1. That the former proceed upon and im- ply principles not got from experience ; that geometry and arith- metic depend on first truths regarding space, time, and number ; and mechanical science on intuitions regarding force, matter, etc. 2. He has exhibited these principles in instructive forms, an- nouncing them in their deeper and wider character under the designation of fundamental ideas, and then presenting them under the name of conceptions in the more specific shapes in which they become available in the particular sciences : thus, in mechanical science the fundamental idea of cause becomes the conception of force. But then he has injured his great work:—1. By fol- lowing the Kantian doctrine of forms, and supposing that the mental ideas “ impose” and “superinduce” on the objects some- thing not in the objects, whereas they merely enable us to arrive at what is in the objects. 2. He also fails to show that the ideas or maxims in the general form in which alone they are available in science, are got by induction. 3. The phraseology which he employs is unfortunate, it is ‘ fundamental ideas ’ and ‘ conceptions.’ The word ‘ idea’ has been used in so many different senses by different writers, by Plato, Descartes, Locke, Kant, and Hegel, that it is perhaps expedient to abandon it altogether in strict philosophic writing ; it is certainly not expedient to use it, as Whewell does, in a new application. The word ‘ conception ’ stands in classical English both for the phantasm, or image, and the logical notion—certain later metaphysicians would restrict it to the logical notion; and there is no propriety in using it to signify an a 'priori law. 4. Pie has damaged the general accep- tance of his principles, which seem to me to be as true as they are often profound, by making a number of truths a priori which are evidently got from experience: thus he makes the law of action and reaction, and the laws of motion generally, self-evident and necessary. PART SECOND. PARTICULAR EXAMINATION OF THE INTUITIONS. 119 BOOK I. PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. CHAPTER I. BODY AND SPIRIT. Sect. I. The Mind begins its Intelligent Acts with Knowledge. The Simple Cognitive Powers. It is a favourite position in the views expounded in this treatise, that the mind begins its acts of intelligence with knowledge. This is not the common representation. According to a very ancient doctrine, the mind has, prior to the acquisition of knowledge, a stock of ideas out of itself, or in itself, at which it looks, and its primary exer- cises consist in contemplating or in forming these ideas. This view, with no pretensions to precision in the state- ment of it, was a prevalent one in ancient Greece, in the scholastic ages, and in the earlier stages of modern phi- losophy. It seems to me to be the view which was ha- bitually entertained by Descartes and Locke. In later times, the mind was supposed to commence with impres- sions of some kind. This view may be regarded as in- troduced formally into philosophy by Hume, who opens his ‘Treatise on Human Nature’ by declaring that all the perceptions of the mind are impressions and ideas ; that impressions come first, and that ideas are the faint images of them. This view has evidently a materialistic ten- 120 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. dency. Literally, an impression can be produced only on a material substance, and it is not easy to determine precisely wliat is meant by the phrase when it is used metaphorically. This impression theory is the one adopted by the French Sensational School, and by the physiologists of this country. In Germany the influence exercised by Kant’s Kritik of Pure Reason has made the general account to be that the mind starts with pre- sentations, and not with things, with phenomena in the sense of appearances, which ‘phenomena’ are but modifi- cations of Hume’s ‘impressions,’ and of the ‘ideas’ of the ancients. Now it appears to me that all these accounts, consciousness being witness, are imperfect, and by their defects erroneous. The mind is not conscious of these impressions preceding the knowledge which it has im- mediately of self, and the objects falling under the notice of the senses. Nor can it be legitimately shown how the mind can ever rise from ideas, impressions, phenomena, to the knowledge of things. The followers of Locke have always felt the difficulty of showing how the mind from mere ideas could reach external realities. Hume designedly represented the original exercises of the mind as being mere impressions, in order to undermine the very foundations of knowledge. Though Kant acknow- ledged a reality beneath the presentations, beyond the phenomena, those who followed out his views found the reality disappearing more and more, till at length it va- nished altogether, leaving only a concatenated series of mental forms. There is no effectual or consistent way of avoiding these consequences but by falling back on the natural system, and maintaining that the mind in its intelligent acts starts with knowledge. But let not the statement be misunderstood. I do not mean that the mind com- mences with abstract knowledge, or general knowledge, BODY AND SPIRIT. 121 or indeed with systematized knowledge of any descrip- tion. It acquires first a knowledge of individual things as they are presented to it and to its knowing faculties, and it is out of this that all its arranged knowledge is formed by a subsequent exercise of the understanding. From the concrete the mind fashions the abstract, by separating in thought a part from the whole, a quality from the object. Starting with the particular, the mind reaches the general by observing the points of agree- ment. From premisses involving knowledge, it can arrive at other propositions also containing knowledge. It seems clear to me, that if the mind had not know- ledge in the foundation, it never could have knowledge in the superstructure reared; but finding knowledge in its first intelligent exercises, it can thence, by the pro- cesses of abstraction, generalization, and reasoning, reach further and higher knowdedge. The mind is endowed with at least two simple cog- nitive powers,—sense-perception and self-consciousness. Both are cognitive in their nature, and look on and re- veal to us existing things; the one, material objects pre- sented to us through the bodily senses, and the other, self in a particular state or exercise. It is altogether inadequate language to represent these faculties as giving us an idea, or an impression, or an apprehension, or a notion, or a conception, or looking on unknown appear- ances, they give us knowledge of objects under aspects presented to us. No other language is equal to express the full mental action of which we are conscious. In this Book it is my aim to seek out, to analyze, and expose to the view the convictions that are involved in the exercise of these two powers. I shall begin with our cognitions in their more concrete form, and then dwell more specially on the cognitions discovered by ab- straction to be involved in these. 122 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. Sect. II. Our Intuitive Cognitions of Body. We are following the plainest dictates of conscious- ness, we avoid a thousand difficulties, and we get a solid ground on which to rest and to build, when we maintain that the mind in its first exercises acquires knowledge; not indeed scientific or arranged, not of qualities of ob- jects and classes of objects, but still knowledge—the knowledge of things presenting themselves, and as they present themselves; which knowledge, individual and concrete, is the foundation of all other knowledge, ab- stract, general, and deductive. In particular, the mind is so constituted as to attain a knowledge of body, or of material objects. It is through the bodily organism that the intelligence of man attains its knowledge of all material objects be- yond. This is true of the infant mind; it is true also of the mature mind. We may assert something more than this regarding the organism. It is not only the medium through which we know all bodily objects beyond itself, it is itself an object primarily known; nay, I am inclined to think that, along with the objects immediately affect- ing it, it is the only object originally known. Intuitively man seems to know nothing beyond his own organism, and objects immediately affecting it; in all further know- ledge there is a process of inference proceeding on a ga- thered experience. This theory seems to me to explain all the facts, and it delivers us from many perplexities. Let us go over the senses one by one, with a view of determining what seems to be the original information supplied by each. In the sense of smell, the objects immediately perceived are the nostrils as affected; it is only by experience that we know that there is an object beyond, from which the smell proceeds, and it is only by science that we know that odorous particles have pro- BODY 123 ceeded from that object. In hearing, our primary per- ceptions seem to be of the ear as affected; that there is a sounding body we learn by further observation, and that there are vibrations between it and the ear we are told by scientific research. In taste, it is originally the palate as affected by what we feel by another sense to be a tangible body, which body science tells us must be in a liquid state. In touch proper, there is a sensation of a particular part of the frame as affected by we know not what, but which we may discover by experiential obser- vation. It is the same with all the impressions we have by the sense of temperature, the sense of titillation, the sense of shuddering, the sense of the creeping of the flesh, the sense of lightness or of weight, and the like organic affections, usually but improperly attributed to touch. In regard to all these senses, it seems highly probable that our original and primitive perceptions are simply of the organism as affected by something unknown, so far as intuition is concerned. But there are other two senses which furnish, I am inclined to think, a new and further kind of information. The sense of touch, when the phrase is used in a loose sense, is a complex one, em- bracing a considerable number and variety of senses, which have not been scientifically classified, and which, perhaps, cannot be so till we have a more thorough physiology of the nerves. Certain it is that there is a locomotive energy and a muscular sense entirely different from feeling, or such affections as those of heat and cold. The soul of man instinctively wills to move the arm ; an action is produced in a motor nerve, which sets in motion a muscle, with probably an attached set of bones, and the intimation of such a movement having taken place is conveyed to the brain by a sensor nerve. As the result of this complex physiological process, we come to know that there is something beyond our organism; we know an object out of our organism hindering the movement 124 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. of the organ and resisting our energy.* It is more dif- ficult to determine what is the original perception by sight. It must certainly be of a coloured surface affecting the felt organism. The boy born blind, when his sight was restored by an operation by Cheselden, felt as if every object “ touched his eyes, as what he felt did his skin.” I think it probable that the coloured‘surface per- ceived as affecting the living organism, is seen as in the direction of the felt and localized sentient organ, neither behind it, nor at the side, but at what distance we know not till other senses and a gathered experience come to our aid. Such seems to be our original knowledge, re- ceived through the various senses as inlets. But we are not to understand that the mind receives sensations and information only from one sense at a time. In order to have a full view of the actual state of things, Ave must remember that man, at every instant of his waking existence, is getting organic feelings and percep- tions from a number of these sources ; say at one and the same time from the sense of heat, from the sense of taste in * The following is the account given by Muller (trans. by Baly, p. 1080):—“ First, the child governs the movements of its limbs, and thus perceives that they are instruments subject to the use and govern- ment of its internal ‘ self,’ while the resistance which it meets with around is not subject to its will, and therefore gives it the idea of an absolute exterior. Secondly, the child will perceive a difference in the sensations produced according as two parts of its own body touch each other, or as one part of its body only meets with resistance from with- out. In the first instance, where one arm, for example, touches the other, the resistance is offered by a part of the child’s own body, and the limb thus giving the resistance becomes the subject of sensation as well as the other. The two limbs are in this case external objects of perception, and percipient at the same time. In the second instance, the resisting body will be represented to the mind as something ex- ternal and foreign to the living body, and not subject to the internal self. Thus will arise in the mind of the child the idea of a resistance which one part of its own body can offer to other parts of its body, and at the same time the idea of a resistance offered to its body by an absolute exterior. In this way is gained the idea of an external world as the cause of sensations.” BODY AND SPIRIT. 125 the mouth, from the sense of hearing, the sense of sight— suppose of a portion of our own body and of the walls of the apartment in which we sit, and from the muscular sense —say ot the chair on which we sit, or the floor on which we stand. Our whole conscious state at any given time is thus a very complex, or rather, a concrete one. There is in it at all times a sense of the living body as extended, and, I may add, as ours. This is a sense which human beings, infant and mature, carry with them every instant of their waking existence, perhaps in a low state even in their times of sleep. “ This consciousness of our own corporeal existence is the standard by which we estimate in our sense of touch the extension of all resisting bo- dies.”* Along with this there will always be in our waking moments a sense of something extra-organic but affecting the organism, such as the surface before the eye, or the object which supports us. But the vividness of the impression made, or some decisive act of the will in order to accomplish a desired end, will at times centre the mind’s regards in a special manner on some one of the objects made known by the senses. Thus, a violent pain in an organ will absorb the whole attention on it- self ; or a vivid colour will draw out the mind towards the coloured object. By these concentrations of intelligence we obtain a more special acquaintance with the nature of the objects presenting themselves. It is thus only that the special senses fulfil their full function, and impart information abiding with us beyond the moment when the action takes place. Such seems to be our original stock of knowledge ac- quired by sense. It is as yet'within very narrow limits, within our frames, and a sphere immediately in contact, f * Muller’s Physiology, translated by Baly, p. 1081. t “ We perceive and can perceive nothing but what is relative to the organ.” (Hamilton, foot-note to Reid, p. 247). 126 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. We reach a wider knowledge by remembering what we have thus obtained, by subjecting it to processes of ab- straction and generalization, and drawing inferences from it. Our information is especially enlarged and consoli- dated, by combining the information got from several of the senses, which are all intended to assist each other. In particular, the two intellectual senses par excellence, sight and the muscular sense, are fitted to aid each other and all the other senses. By sight we know merely a co- loured surface; by the muscular sense we may come to know that the object with a superficies has three dimen- sions and is impenetrable,—we may know the object to be the same by our seeing upon it the hand which feels the pressure. By sight we know not how far the co- loured surface is from our organism; by inferences founded on gathered information from the muscular sense, we come to know how far it is from us, whether an inch or many feet or yards. By the muscular sense we know solid objects only as pressing themselves immediately on our organism ; by sight we see objects—which sight does not declare to be solid but which a combined experience declares must be solid—thousands or millions of miles away. By inferences from various senses united, we know that this taste is from a certain kind of food, that this smell is from a rose or lily, that this sound is from a human voice or a musical instrument. Thus our knowledge, commencing with the organism and objects affecting it, may extend to objects at a great distance, and clothe them with qualities which are not perceived as immediately belonging to them. We know that this blue surface seen indistinctly is a bay of the ocean fifty miles off, and that this brilliant spark up in the blue concave, is a solid body, radiating light hundreds of mil- lions of miles away. Let us analyse what is involved in this intuitive know- ledge. BODY 127 I. We know the object as existing or having be- ing. This is a necessary conviction, attached to, or rather, composing an essential part of our concrete cognition of every material object presented to us, be it our own frame, or of things external to our frame; whether this hard table or stone, or this yielding water, or even this vapoury mist, or this fleeting cloud. We look on each of the objects thus presented to us, in our organism or be- yond it, as having an existence, a being, a reality. Every one understands these phrases ; they cannot be made simpler or more intelligible by an explanation. We un- derstand them because they express a mental fact which every one has experienced. We may talk of what we contemplate in sense-perception being nothing but an impression, an appearance, an idea, but we can never be made to give our assent to any such statements. However ingenious the arguments which may be adduced in favour of the objects of our sense-perceptions being mere illusions, we find that after listening to them, and allowing to them all the weight that is possible, we still look upon bodies as realities next time they present themselves. The rea- son, is we know them to be realities, by a native cogni- tion which can never be overcome. II. In our primitive cognitions, we know objects as having an existence independent of the contemplative mind. We know the object as separate from ourselves. We do not create it when we perceive it, nor does it cease to exist because we have ceased to contemplate it. All this is involved in our very cognition of the object, and he who would deny this is setting aside our very primitive knowledge, and he who would argue against this, will never be able to convince us in fact, because he is opposing a fundamental conviction which will work whenever the object is presented.* * Tlie convictions referred to in these paragraphs, set aside at once 128 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. III. We know the object as having an abiding exist- ence. This is a truth which requires to be stated with not a few explanations and cautions. I can merely give a hint of what is meant, and reserve the fuller discussion of it till I come to speak of substance, in the next chap- ter. I have already affirmed that every material object has an existence abiding, in this sense, that our contem- plation did not create it, nor will it cease to exist because our attention is not directed towards it. But this is not all: we apprehend that this thing has an abiding being in itself. Our intuition indeed does not say, as to this being, how or when it came to be there, nor whether nor in what circumstances it may cease; for information on such topics we must go to other quarters. But when the question is started, we must decide that this thing had a being prior to our perceiving it, unless indeed it so happened that it was produced by a power capable of doing so at the very time our senses alighted on it, and that it will continue to exist after we have ceased to re- gard it, unless indeed something interpose to destroy it. But enough for the present of this somewhat difficult discussion. IV. In our primitive cognition of body there is in- volved a knowledge of outness or externality.* We tlie doctrine of Kaut, that the mind in the intuition of sense, takes cognizance of phenomena in the sense of appearances. They should also modify the doctrine of Hamilton. “ Our knowledge of qualities or phenomena is necessarily relative, for these exist only as they exist in relation to our faculties.” (Foot-note to Eeid, p. 323.) It is a tru- ism that we can know objects merely as our faculties enable us to know them; but the question is, What is the nature and extent of the know- ledge which our faculties furnish ? I admit that whatever external ob- jects we know, we know in a relation to us. But I hold that man and his faculties are so constituted as to know things (with being) exer- cising qualities, and to know qualities as existing separate from and in- dependent of our cognition of them. * “ Perception involves in every instance the notion of externality, or outness” (D. Stewart, Essays, p. 419). BODY. 129 know the object perceived, be it the organism or the object affecting the organism, as not in the mind, as out of the mind. In regard to some of the objects perceived by us we may be in doubt as to whether they are in the organism or beyond it, but we are always sure that they are extra-mental. This is a conviction from which we can never be driven by any power of will or force of cir- cumstances. It is at the foundation of the judgments to be afterwards specified as to the distinctions between the self and the not-self, the ego and the non-ego* Y. In all our knowledge through the senses we know the object as extended. I am inclined to think that this knowledge in the concrete is involved even in such per- ceptions as those of smell, taste, hearing, and feeling, and the allied affections of temperature and titillation. In all these we intuitively know the organism as out of the mind, as extended, and as localized. At every waking moment we have sensations from more than one sense, and we must know the organs affected as out of each other and in different places, f It is acknowledged that the primitive * The convictions spoken of in these paragraphs set aside all forms of idealism in sense-perception. Berkeley says that, so far as matter is concerned, “ esse est per dpi." I hold, that according to our intuitive conviction, the thing which we perceive must exist before we can per- ceive it, and that we perceive it as an extended thing independent and out of the contemplative mind. Fichte represents the external thing as a creation or projection of the perceiving mind. But the mind in knowing the self as perceiving, knows that it is an external thing that is perceived, and cannot he made to think otherwise. Pro- fessor Ferrier bases his fabric of demonstrated idealism on the propo- sition, the object of knowledge “ always is, and must he, the object with the addition of oneself,—object plus subject,—thing, or thought, mecum” (Inst, of Metaph. prop. ii.). If this proposition professes to be a statement of fact, I deny that the fact of consciousness is properly stated. If it professes to be a first truth, I deny that it ought to be assumed in this particular form. No doubt we always know self at the same time that we know an external object by sense-perception, but we know the external object as separate from and independent of self. We might as well deny that we know the object at all, as deny that we know it to have an existence distinct from self t Hamilton says, “ An extension is apprehended in the apprehension 130 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. knowledge got in this way is very bare and limited, and without those perceived relationships and distinctions which become associated with it in our future life. But imperfect though it be, it must ever involve the occupa- tion of space. The other two senses furnish more express information, the eye giving a coloured surface of a de- fined form, and the muscular sense extension in three dimensions. It should be noticed that in our knowledge of extra-organic objects, whether by the eye or the mus- cular sense, we know them as situated in a certain place in reference to our organism, which we have already so far localized and distributed in space, and which henceforth we use as a centre for direction and distance. VI. We know the objects as affecting us. I have al- ready said that we know them as independent of us. This is an important truth. But it is equally true and equally important that these objects are made known to us as somehow having an influence on us. The or- ganic object is capable of affecting our minds, and the extra-organic object affects the organism which affects the mind. Upon this cognition are founded certain judg- ments as to the relations of the object known to the knowing mind. In particular, VII. In certain, if not in all, of our original cognitions through the senses we know the objects as exercising potency or property. This is denied in theory by many who are yet found to admit it inadvertently when they tell us that we can know matter only by its properties: for what, I ask, are properties but powers to act in a certain way? But still it is dogmatically asserted, that whatever we may know about material objects, we can of the reciprocal externality of all sensations” (Appendix to Reid, p. 885). Again, “ In the consciousness of sensations relatively localized and reciprocally external, we have a veritable apprehension and conse- quently an immediate perception of the affected organism, as extended, divided, figured, etc.” (ib. p. 884). BODY 131 never know that they have power; we cannot see power, they say, nor hear power, nor touch power. In oppo- sition to these confident assertions, I lay down the very opposite dogma, that we cannot see body, or touch, or even hear, or taste, or smell body, except as affecting us, that is, having a power in reference to us. When an extra-organic body resists our muscular energy,* what is it doing but affecting our organism in a certain way ? The very coloured surface revealed through sight, is known to us as affecting, that is, having an influence over, our organism. But there is more than this,—the organism is known as having power to affect the cog- nitive self. The muscular effort resisted, the visual or- gans impressed by the coloured surface, are known as pro- ducing an effect on the mind. The organs affected in smell, in taste, in temperature, in hearing, in feeling, are all known as rousing the mind into cognitive activity. It might be further maintained, even in regard to those senses which do not immediately reveal anything extra- organic, that they seem to point to some unknown cause of the affection known; but it is better to postpone the discussion of this question till it can be discussed fully. But in regard to the two senses which reveal objects be- yond the bodily frame, and in regard to all the senses so far as they make known our frame to us, there is an intuitive conviction of potency wrapped up in all our cog- nitions. But it will be vehemently urged that it is most pre- * Locke says that impenetrability, or, as lie prefers calling it, as having less of a negative meaning, solidity, seems the “ idea most inti- mately connected with and essential to body, so as nowhere else to be found or imagined, but only in matterand he adds, we “ find it in- separably inherent in body wherever or however modifiedand in explaining this, he says of bodies, that “ they do by an unsurmountable force hinder the approach of the parts of our hands that press them ” (Essay, ii. iv. 1). 132 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. posterous to assert that we know all this by the senses. Upon this I remark that the phrase by the senses is am- biguous. If by senses be meant the mere bodily or- ganism,—the eye, the ears, the nerves, and the brain,— I affirm that we know, and can know, nothing by this mere bodily part; that so far from knowing potency or extension, we do not know even colour, or taste, or smell. But if by the senses be meant the mind exercised in sense-perception, summoned into activity by the organ- ism, and contemplating cognitively the external world, then I maintain that we do know, and this intuitively, external objects as influencing us—that is, exercising powers in reference to us. I ask those who would doubt of this doctrine, of what it is that they suppose the mind to be cognizant in sense-perception. If they say, a mere sensation or impression in the mind, I reply that this is not consistent with the revelation of con- sciousness, which announces plainly that what we know is something extra-mental. If they say, with Kant, a mere phenomenon in the sense of appearance, then I reply that this too is inconsistent with consciousness, which declares that we know the thing. But if we know the thing, we must know something about it. If they say they know it as having extension and form, I grasp at the admission, and ask them to consider how high the knowledge thus allowed, involving at one and the same time space, and an object occupying space, and so much of space. Surely those who acknowledge this much may be prepared to confess further that the mind which in perception is capable of knowing an object as occu- pying space, is also capable of knowing the same object as exercising power in regard to us.* We have only to * “ C’est la raison, et la raison seule, qui connait, et connait le monde ; et elle ne le connait d’abord qu’a titre de cause ; il n’est d’abord pour nous que la cause des pbenomenes sensitifs que nous ne pouvons nous rapporter a nous-memes; et nous ne rechercherions pas cette BODY 133 examine the state of mind involved in all our cognitions of matter, to discover that there is involved in it a know- ledge both of extension and of property. Such seem to be some of the principal of our cog- nitions through the senses; and I have sought to evolve them by an analysis proceeding on a careful observation of their nature. Sect. III. Some Distinctions to be Attended to in Regard to our Cognition of Body. It is a fundamental position with the author of this treatise that we ought to look on all our primitive cog- nitions as guaranteeing a reality. In particular we are to look on each of our sense-perceptions as pointing to a corresponding extra-mental object. But in order to be able to maintain this doctrine with even the appearance of plausibility, it is necessary to attend to certain dis- tinctions. cause, par consequent nous ne la trouverions pas, si notre raison n’etait pourvue du principe de causalite, si nous pouvions supposer qu’un phe- nomene peut commencer a apparaitre sur le theatre de la conscience, du temps ou de l’espace, sans qu’il ait une cause. Done le principe de causalite, je ne crains pas de le dire, est le pere du monde exterieur, loin qu’il soit possible de l’en tirer, et de le faire venir de la sensation.” So says M. Cousin in criticizing Locke (Deux. Ser. tom. iii. L9. 19). This is not far from the truth. There is reason or intelligence involved in our knowledge of the external world, and there is causality in this knowledge. The mind knows the external thing as a cause—it must know it in other characters as well, in particular it must know it as extended—still, it knows it as a cause. But except in the mode of development, this doctrine does not differ so much from that of Locke as Cousin imagines. Locke derives the materials of all our ideas from sensation and experience. He derives our idea of cause from both these sources. But then the mind, in the formation of its ideas, proceeds intel- ligently, reasonably. There is intelligence, according to Locke, in sen- sation, and in comparing certain ideas the mind perceives their agree- ment immediately by intuition. Locke’s account of the full pheno- menon does not seem to me satisfactory, or very congruously wrought out; but it is quite as near the truth as that of Cousin, -who calls sen- sation the chronological condition, and reason the logical principle (See this distinction examined, infra, Part III. Bk. I. Ch. II. sect. v.). 134 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. I. There is the Distinction between our Original and Acquired Perceptions. In standing up for the trustworthiness of our perceptions, I always mean our original perceptions, proceeding from the primitive prin- ciples of the mind, and having the sanction of Him who gave us our constitution. The perceptions acquired by inference, or other intellectual processes grounded on experience, will have a corresponding reality only when these processes have been validly conducted. I have endeavoured in last Section to give an approxi- mately correct account of what seem to be our original perceptions through the various senses. But to our primitive stock we add others, and in doing so we em- ploy rules derived from the generalizations of experience, and deductive reasoning in applying them to given cases. It has been all but universally acknowledged, since the days of Berkeley, that the perception of distance is not an original endowment of the sense of sight in human beings, but that we come to determine it by a gathered observation. As the result of experience, we lay down such rules as these: that an object with whose form we are familiar,—such as a watch,—if seen with a faint colour and outline, and with a smaller disc in comparison with other known objects in the field of view, must be more distant than when seen with a better defined figure and a more vivid colour and a fuller form. We lay it down as another rule, that when a number of objects inter- vene between us and a scene on which we are looking,— say a mountain,—it must be at a considerable distance. Such rules formed by us are found approximately cor- rect, and useful in ordinary cases, and at every instant at which our eyes are open they conduct us to a knowledge which carries us far beyond our primitive perceptions. But then it is to be noticed that error may creep into our acquired perceptions. We may reckon a rule as BODY 135 universal which has many exceptions, and may make an application of it to a wrong case. It will not be difficult to show that all the supposed deception of the senses is to be traced to the wrong inferences which we draw in our acquired perceptions. Almost all forms of idealism—the system which sup- poses certain of our supposed cognitions to be creations of the mind, and all forms of scepticism—the system which would set aside all our cognitions, plead the deceitful- ness of the senses. Our senses are not to be trusted in some things, says the idealist, and we are to determine by reason wrhen they are to be trusted. Our senses de- lude us in some things, says the sceptic, and we may therefore distrust them in all. It is of vast moment to stop these errors at the point at which they flow out, by showing that the senses, meaning our original percep- tions through the senses, can all be trusted in regard to the special testimony which they furnish. But how, it is asked, does the stick in the water, felt to be straight by the sense of touch, seem crooked to the sense of sight ? The answer is, that the knowledge of the shape of an object does not primarily fall under the sense of sight, and that when we determine whether a stick is or is not straight, by the sense of sight, it is by a process of inference in which we have laid down the rule that objects that give a certain figure before the eye are crooked, a rule correct enough for common cases, but not applicable to cases in which the rays of light are re- fracted in passing from one medium to another. Why does a boy seem a man, and a man a giant in a mist, whereas if you clear away the mist, both are instantly re- duced to their proper dimensions ? An answer can ea- sily be given. We have laid down the rule that an object seen so dimly must be distant; but an object appearing of such dimensions at a distance must be large : and the 13 G PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. phenomenon is felt to be a deception only by those who are not accustomed to move in the mist. Why does a mountain, viewed across an arm of the sea, seem near, while the same mountain, seen at an equal distance be- yond an undulated country studded with houses and trees, will seem very remote ? The answer is not that the eye has deceived us, but that we have made a mis- taken application of a rule usually correct, that an object must be near when few objects intervene between us and it; and it is to be noticed that those who are accus- tomed to look across sheets of water, commit no such mistakes, for they have acquired other means of measur- ing distance. Again, we have found it true in cases so many, that we cannot number them, that when we are at rest and the image of an object, say a carriage, passes across the vision, the object must be in motion. That rule is accurate in all cases similar to those from which it was derived ; but it fails the landsman when, feeling as if he were at rest in the ship, he infers that the shore is moving away from the vessel. In all such cases we see that it is not the senses, that is, the natural and original perceptions of the senses having the authority of God, which deceive us, but rules formed by ourselves, and il- legitimately applied. It may be observed that the same experience which enables us to gather the rules, may enable us to ascertain the limits of the rules, and the ex- ceptions. It is only the landsman who is deceived into the thought that the shore is moving; the seaman has modified the rule, or rather, he realizes the idea that he himself is moving, and he is not deceived for one instant. Supposing this to be the correct account, we may stand up for the trustworthiness of all our intuitive perceptions, at least when the organism and the mind are in a healthy state. Even in cases in which the organism is diseased, the error lies commonly, perhaps always, in a wrong in- BODY. 137 ference.* When our visual organs are distempered, we may seem to see a solid figure before us which touch tells us has no reality; but the fact is, all that we intuitively see is a coloured surface, whether in or out of the organ- ism, whether solid or aerial, we know not intuitively. We hear a sound which we interpret as coming from a voice where no living being can be, but the interpretation is our own : all that our nature declares is, that there is an affection of our auditory organs. The visions, the ima- ginary sounds, touches, and smells, felt by persons whose organs are diseased, or excited by strong mental fancy within—just as they would be by an object without, are, after all, inferences from what are in themselves mere or- ganic affections. In the greater number of such cases, there is a means of detecting the error occasioned by dis- ease in one of the organs, by other organs not distem- pered. At the same time I am not inclined to deny that there may be cases in which the brain is so disorgan- ized, and the mind so deranged, that the person is given up for life to hopeless delusion. We are now within the * Aristotle had an apprehension of what I am convinced will turn out to be the true account of these seeming errors of the senses. (See his Treatise on the Soul, b. iii., c. i., iii., vi.) He says the perception, by a sense, of things peculiar to that sense, is true, or invol ves the small- est amount of error. But when such objects are perceived in their ac- cidents (that is, as to things not falling peculiarly under that sense), there is room for falsehood ; when, for instance, something is said to be white there is no falsehood, but wThen the object is said to be this or that (if the white thing is said to be Cleon), (cf. iii., i. 7), there may be falsehood. 'H a’ladrjais twv pev 18lav aXrjBrjs iariv t) oti (Sklyarov eyoixra to \fsev8os. devrepov 8e rod o-vpj3efir)Kevai ravra- /cat ivravOa fj8r] ephemeral dia-y/sevdeo-Oai• oti pev yap Aevicov, ov \/sevSerai, ei 8e tovto to XevKov 77 aAAo tl yfretjdeTai (iii., iii., 12 : ed. Trendelenburg). ’AAV Snnvep to opav tov 181ov aXr/des, el 8’ avdpanros to Aevnov rj pi], ovk aXrjdes aiei (ib. vi. 7). Aristotle saw that the difficulties might be cleared up, by attending to what each sense testifies, and separating the associated imaginations and opi- nions or judgments. The full explanation, however, could not be given till Berkeley led men to distinguish between the original and acquired perceptions of the senses, by showing that the know ledge of distance by the eye, is an acquisition. 138 primitive cognitions. range of phenomena which carry us into the deepest mysteries of our world, and have a connection with man’s liability to disease, and the existence of sin. II. There is the Distinction between Sensation and Perception. It may be laid down as a general fact, that every given state of man’s mind is concrete; that is, in the one act there are elements which may be separated at other times, or which may be separated by analysis. Thus in purely mental action, there may at one and the same moment be an exercise of the intelligence, of feeling, and of will; in one act we may comprehend that our friend is in distress, may feel grieved in conse- quence, and resolve to take steps to relieve him. In like manner all the mental affections excited by the action of the bodily senses are concrete. What is thus mixed up in one concrete act, can be separated by analysis, and ought for important ends to be so separated : indeed the sepa- ration is often made for us naturally, for we have now one portion, and now another of the combined state. In particular, it is of great moment in philosophy to distin- guish between the sensations and perceptions which are always mixed up together. Perception is the knowledge of the object presenting itself to the senses, whether in the organism or beyond it. Sensation is the feeling associated,—the feeling of the organism. These two always coexist.* There is never the knowledge without an organic feeling, never a feeling of the organism without a cognitive apprehen- sion of it. These sensations differ widely from each other, as our consciousness testifies ; some of them being pleasant, some painful; others indifferent as to pleasure * Reid represents the sensation being “ followed by a perception of the objecton which Hamilton remarks, “ that sensation proper pre- cedes perception proper is a false assumption ; they are simultaneous elements of the same indivisible energy” (Reid’s Works, p. 186: see also p. 853). BODY. 139 and pain, but still with a feeling. Some we call ex- citing, others dull; some we designate as warm, others as cold; and for most of them we have no name what- ever,—indeed they so run into each other that it would be difficult to discriminate them by a specific nomen- clature. The perceptions, again, are as numerous and varied as the knowledge we have by all the senses. Now these two ever mix themselves up with each other. The sensation of the odour mingles with the apprehension of the nostrils; the flavour of the food is joined with the recognition of the palate; the agreeableness or disagree- ableness of the sound comes in with the knowledge of the ear as affected; and the organ which we know as feeling has an associated sensation. There is an organic sensation conjoined even with the knowledge we have of the extra-organic object affecting our muscular sense or our visual organism. This sensation may be little noticed because the attention is fixed on the object; still it is always there, as we may discover by a careful introspection of the combined mental affection. But this leads me to notice that in the concrete men- tal state sometimes the perception or the knowledge is the more prominent, whereas at other times the sensa- tion is the predominant. There is a difference indeed of the senses in this respect. Thus in the senses of taste, smell, touch proper, and the allied senses of tem- perature, titillation, shuddering, and flesh-creeping, the sensation is the prevailing element. These may be regarded as the lower and the more animal senses, in which the attention is largely absorbed in self. In hear- ing, so far as the original perceptions are concerned, the sensation is still the predominant affection; but as we come to know the sounding bodies, our attention is often directed almost exclusively to the object. Thus as we are listening to a person speaking we lose sight of the 140 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. hearing ear, and think only of what is said. Still, when the sounds are unpleasant, or when they are peculiarly pleasant, as in music, it is the sensation that absorbs the attention. In the muscular sense it is the resisting ob- ject that is most noticed. In sight the colour is largely (but not exclusively, as will be shown forthwith) a sen- sational, whereas the spread-out surface is the perceptive element. In many of our acts of vision there is a nice balancing of the two, the colour and the form being alike noticed; in others the colour, by its gorgeousness, ab- sorbs the whole mental energy; while in a third class the colour-sensation is lost sight of, and we are conscious of scarcely anything more than the form. And here I am tempted to remark that in the lower forms, both of nature and of the fine arts, it is the colour which is the more striking characteristic; and children, and persons low in the scale of intelligence, feel a peculiar delight in such objects. As we rise, in nature to the common her- baceous plants, and in art to flower-painting, there is often a union of the beauty, both of colour and of form. When we mount to the highest plants, as to the trees of the forest, and to the animal creation and the human form, and in art to historical painting, varied colouring disappears, that higher minds may gaze with undivided attention on objective forms characterized by high propor- tions, or full of life or suggestive of character. It should not be omitted that the mind can at any time fix its attention more specially on one of these, and then the other will very much disappear from the field of view. Sometimes this is done for us spontaneously, by the vividness of the sensation on the one hand, or by the interest which collects around the external object on the other. Sometimes the concentration is effected by a strong act of will, fixing the mind’s regards on one or other in order to gain a special end. Thus we may BODY. 141 yield ourselves entirely to a luscious strain of music, or we may be absorbed in thought about some object, so as scarcely to notice the sounds. Under ear-ache we may have the whole energy of the mind concentred on the pain, and be able to attend to nothing else; or we may be so interested in a discourse or a topic of thought as scarcely to feel the torture. But while the two ever coexist,—sometimes with the one prevailing and sometimes with the other predomi- nant, and sometimes with the two nicely balanced, it is of importance to distinguish them. Every man of sense draws the distinction between the music and the mu- sical instrument, between the ear-ache and his ear. The metaphysician should also draw the distinction,—indeed it is essential that he do so. The two were given for different ends. Our perceptions are the main means of supplying us with knowledge, whereas our sensations are meant to increase our enjoyment, to stimulate to ex- ertion, to give warning, or perhaps to inflict penalties. We must beware, both philosophically and practically, of confounding our sensations and our perceptions, our feelings and our cognitions. In the confounding of the two we have another circumstance leading men to charge their senses with deception. This will appear more fully when we come to notice another set of dis- tinctions. III. There are Distinctions between the Objects Known. There is the distinction between the organic object and the object beyond the organism. There is the more delicate distinction between the objects imme- diately known as extra-organic and objects inferred as affecting the organism but themselves unknown. Let me explain these, distinctions. We have seen that in some of the senses the proper object of perception is the organism itself. In two others 142 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. it is beyond the organism. Let us consider these two classes in order. In the first class all that we know immediately is the organism as affected. But if affected, it must be affected by something. It is in one state this instant, and it will be in another state the next. The intuitive con- viction of causation—to be afterwards discussed—con- strains us to look for an agent to produce the effect. And where is this agent to be found? In the organism, or beyond the organism? I am certain, in regard to some of our organic affections, that intuition says nothing on this special point. This is the case with our sense of smell, our taste and touch, and sense of temperature,— and I think also, though with some hesitation, of the sense of hearing. The intuitive conviction of cause and effect does indeed intimate that there must be a cause, but as to where that cause is to be found we must trust to experience, which tells us that the cause is in some cases to be found in the organism itself, and in other cases in an agent beyond,—such as odorous particles, sapid bodies, heat, undulations from a sounding body, or a solid object applied to our nerves of touch. In all cases the affection of sense and the conviction of cause combined are sufficient to prompt us to look round for an agent. The senses act as monitors, and most im- portant monitors they are, of powers working in our bodily frames, and in the physical universe around us. I believe that every one of our senses gives us intimation of powers,—such as floating particles, light, and heat, which are among the most powerful agencies conducting the processes of the material world. Still these are un- known to our senses, and we become aware of their ex- istence merely as causes of known effects. As to what odours, sounds, flavours, heat, and, we may add, light and colours are, our intuitions are silent, and their na- body. 143 ture is to be determined by observation,—indeed can be determined only by elaborate scientific research. It should be added, that while science has ascertained much about them, it has not, in its latest advances, been able to settle what is the exact nature of such agents as heat, light, and colour. Let us turn now to the other class of senses, which give us a knowledge of extra-organic objects. By the muscular sense we know an object as extended in three dimensions, and as resisting our effort. We have thus a knowledge of objects extended, and exercising dyna- mic energy beyond the little world of self. The sense of sight presents peculiar difficulties in this connection. It seems to me clearly to look at an extended surface, not part of our organism, but affecting it. But what are we to make of colour ? It is the greatest diffi- culty which the metaphysician meets with in the investi- gation of the senses. The mind knows the perceived object to be in its nature extended; but do we also know it as in its very nature coloured ? If so, is there colour in the object as there is extension? The follow- ing is the solution which I am inclined to offer of this difficult subject. The sense of colour may be regarded as intermediate between those senses in which we per- ceive an extra-organic object, and those other senses which reveal merely the organism as affected, but whether by agents within or beyond the organism we know not. In the sense of colour, we primarily know only the or- ganism as affected, but we are intuitively led, at the same time, to look on what thus affects our organism as not in the organism, but as in the extended surface in which it is seen. But beyond this, that is beyond colour being an extra-organic cause of an organic af- fection, we know nothing of its nature by intuition. If this account be correct, we see that our sense of co- 144 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. lour is different, on the one hand, from our know- ledge of our sensations of heat, or smell, or taste, for we do not know whether these are within or beyond the frame, while we do know that colour is out of ourselves in a surface; and different, too, on the other hand, from the knowledge of the extended surface and the impene- trability which are revealed directly by the sight and muscular sense, whereas we do not know what colour is. Hence arises, if I do not mistake, that peculiar conviction regarding colour which has so puzzled metaphysicians. The sense of colour combines, in closest union, the sen- sation and the perception, the organic affection and the extra-organic. I confess I have always fondly clung to the idea that, sooner or later, colour will be found by physical investigation to have a reality, I do not say of what kind, in every material object.* By help of such distinctions as these, we may defend the validity of all our native convictions through the senses. In doing so, it will be observed that we stand up for the trustworthiness of our original, but not ne- cessarily of our acquired perceptions; that we stand up for a reality corresponding to our perceptions proper, but not therefore to our associated sensations; and that we stand up for a reality, be it organic, or extra-organic, or both, corresponding to each particular sense as for itself, but not a reality for any one sense of precisely the same kind as the reality for the others. The senses can be supposed to deceive us, when the organism and mind are in a sound state, only when we overlook one or other or all of these distinctions. * I have, in ‘Typical Forms and Special Ends,’ by J. M‘Cosh and Geo. Dickie (p. 165, 2nd ed.), pointed to a number of phenomena, which seem to show that colour is a reality in the object, which reality is made known to us by means of the reflection of the beam by the colour. When the undivided beam falls on the green leaves of a plant, the green beam is reflected aud reaches our eye, and the red is absorbed, not to be lost, but to come out in russet bark, or red flower, or berry. BODY. 145 Sect. IV. The Qualities of Matter known by Intuition. The distinctions unfolded in last Section seem to be the all-important ones, in order to enable us to defend the trustworthiness of our sense-perceptions. I have not, in that Section, made mention of the famous distinction between the Primary and Secondary Qualities of Matter, because, so far as it is fitted to clear up and establish the validity of the senses, it is embraced in those which we have drawn, and which are fitted, in my opinion, to bring out the whole truth in a fuller and more distinct manner. But it will be necessary, for other philosophic ends, to draw a distinction between the qualities of matter which are primitively known, and others which may become known by induction or scientific research. The qualities of matter known to intuition may be divided into three classes:—those which relate to space; those which one body exercises in reference to another; those which body exercises in reference to the sensitive and perceiving mind. Let it be observed, in regard to all of these, that the quality in the body always relates to something else, so passive and dependent is body on something out of itself. I. There are the Qualities of Matter by which it occu- pies Space and is contained in Space, that is, Extension. We have this knowledge, I believe, through each of our senses; for in each of our senses we know the corre- sponding organs as extended and out of each other, and through two of the senses we know objects beyond our bodily frame as extended. Hamilton represents exten- sion as a necessary constituent of our notion of Matter, and evolves it from “ two catholic conditions of matter; (I.) the occupying space, and (II.) the being contained in space. Of these, the former affords (A) Trinal Exten- sion, explicated again into (i.) Divisibility, (u.) Size, con- 140 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. taining under it Density or Rarity, (hi.) Figure, and (B) Ultimate Incompressibility; while the latter gives (A) Mobility, and (B) Situation. Neglecting subordination, we have thus eight proximate attributes; 1, Extension; 2, Divisibility; 3, Size; 4, Density or Rarity; 5, Figure; 0, Incompressibility absolute; 7, Mobility; 8, Situation.”* II. The Qualities which one body exercises in reference to another; in other words, the Properties or Forces of matter. I have expended much labour in vain if I have not shown, in previous Sections, that here we have a necessary conviction. In the visual and locomotive senses, we know an extra-organic object as affecting us and our organism. All this seems to be involved in our perception, and to be a native conviction of the mind, to which it is ever prompted, and from which it can never be delivered. Not only so, we are ever led to look for a producing cause, even of our purely organic affections in the ear and palate and nostrils. A knowledge of power, and a conviction of power being in exercise, is thus involved in our very perceptions through the senses. Adhering to these views, we must set aside at once two opposite doctrines which have had the support each of a number of eminent metaphysicians or metaphysical speculators. The one is that matter is known as possess- ing no other quality than extension. This error origi- nated with Descartes,f and has prevailed extensively among those metaphysicians who have felt his influence. But the view is opposed to that intuition which repre- sents all matter as having and exercising energy. On the other side, there are speculators who maintain that all the phenomena of matter can be explained by suppo- * Hamilton’s Reid, Note D, p. 848. t “ L’espace ou le lieu interieur et le corps qui est compris en cet espace, ne sont differents aussi que par notre pensee. Car, en effet la meme etendue en longueur, largeur et profondeur qui constitue l’espace constitue le corps” (Des. Med. p. ii. 10). BODY. 147 sing it to possess potency. This mistake sprang from Leibnitz, who supposed that the universe of matter (and of mind) was composed of monads having power, and to which the mind imparted the relation of space.* But the dynamical theory of body, so far as it denies the ex- istence of space, and body as occupying space, is ut- terly inconsistent with that fundamental conviction, of which the mind can never be shorn, which declares that the matter which has force must be extended, and that the force exercised is a force in a body in one part of space, over another body in a different part of space. III. There is the influence, that is, power, which the bodily organs have over the mind. I feel that I must speak with great caution on this topic. Neither physio- logy nor psychology has been able to throw any light on the particular way in which body affects mind. The theories which have been introduced,—such as that of Occasional Causes by the disciples of Descartes, and of Pre-established Harmony by Leibnitz, and of impressions by modern physiologists,—have only increased, instead of removing the difficulties. We cannot say whether the organism affects the knowing mind immediately or me- diately. We cannot say whether it has power in itself, or whether the power may not lie in some other agent working in the organ. We cannot say whether the power lies exclusively in the organ, or, as is more probable, in the organ and mind combined. Scientific research has thrown no light on these mysteries, and intuition should not pretend to settle these questions. Still intuition seems to me to say, that connected with the organism * Leibnitz lield that bodies are endowed with some sort of active force. “ Les corps sont doues de quelque force active.” This force may be called life. “ C’est une realite immaterielle, indivisible et indestructi- ble : il en met partout dans le corps croyant qu’il n’y a point de partie de la masse ou il n’y ait un corps organise, doue de quelque perception ou d’une maniere d’ame (Op. p. 694: ed. Erdmann). That he looked upon space as a relation will come out below. 148 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. there is power of some kind to call forth mental ac- tion. Such seem to be the qualities of matter which we know by intuition. But even in regard to these, experi- ence is ever adding to our knowledge, which we arrange and systematize by induction and science. Whatever other qualities of matter—if there be such—may become known to us, are discovered by experience. I have put the qualification if there be such, because in fact we do not know whether all the other qualities of body be not modifications of those we have named. We are made aware of such agents as heat, light, electricity, magnetism, but it is an unsettled question whether they are bodies or (as is more probable) affections of body, implying forces of a peculiar character. These are questions which can be determined only by physical science, proceeding in the method of induction. Sect. Y. Our Intuitive Cognition op Self or of Spirit. It is very probable (tbougb it can never be positively proven) that the first knowledge acquired by the mind is of our own bodily frame, through the sensitive organism —a view which does not imply that, apart altogether from such perceptions, the spirit would not have ope- rated. But whatever may be the theory formed on this speculative subject, it is certain that whenever or how- ever the mind is aroused into an act of intelligence, there is always involved in the exercise a knowledge of self. Coexisting with every intelligent act of mind there is always a self-consciousness. But let it be carefully observed that this knowledge is not of an abstract being or substance, or of an ego, or of an essence, but of the concrete self in the particular state in which it may be, with the particular thoughts, sensations, or purposes, which it may be entertaining at the time. Let us ob- SPIRIT. 149 serve, and seek to evolve, what is involved in the cognition of self. I. We know self as having being, existence. The knowledge we have in self-consciousness, which is asso- ciated with every intelligent act, is not of an impression, as Hume would say, nor of a mere quality or attribute, as certain of the Scottish metaphysicians* would affirm, nor of a phenomenon, in the sense of appearance, as Kantf supposes, but of a thing or reality. In affirming this, we are bringing out and expressing what is embraced in our primitive cognition. No account which falls short of this can be regarded as a full exhibition of the facts falling under our eye when we look within. If any man main- '* The Scottish School generally maintains that we do not know mind and body, but only the qualities of them. Reid indeed says, “ Every man is conscious of a thinking principle, or mind, in himself” (Works, p. 217). Campbell, in his ‘ Philosophy of Rhetoric,’ speaks of con- sciousness being concerned with “the existence of mind itself, and its actual feelings, etc.” (b. i. c. v. p. ii.). But this language is not free from ambiguity. Reid says that “ sensation suggests to us both a faculty and a mind, and not only suggests the notion of them, but creates a belief of their existenceand he defends the use of the word ‘ suggest,’ which I reckon a very unfortunate one in such an applica- tion (Works, pp. 110-111). This view is carried out and elaborated by D. Stewart: “ It is not matter or body which I perceive by my senses, but only extension, figure, colour, and certain other qualities, which the constitution of my nature leads me to refer to something which is extended, figured, and coloured. The case is precisely similar with respect to mind. We are not immediately conscious of its existence, but we are conscious of sensation, thought, and volition, operations which imply the existence of something which feels, thinks, and wills ” (Elem. vol. i. p. 46). See also vol. ii. p. 41, and Phil. p. 58. t Kant holds that the inner sense gives no intuition of the soul as an object. “ Der innere Sinn, vermittelst dessen das Gremuth sich selbst, oder seinen inneren Zustand anseliaut, giebt zwar keine An- schauung von der Seele selbst, als einem Object” (Kr. d. r. Y. p. 34). He speaks of the subject envisaging itself, not as it is, but as it appears : “Da es denn sich selbst anschaut, nicht wie es sich unmittelbar selbst- thatig vorstellen wiirde, sondern nach der Art wie es von innem afficirt wird, folglich wie es sich erscheint, nicht wie es ist” (Zw. Aufg. p. 718). He says that by the inner sense we know the subject self as phenome- non, and not as it is in itself: “ Was die innere Anschauung betrifl't, 150 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. tains that all that we can discover is a mere idea, impres- sion, phenomenon, or quality of an unknown thing, I ask him for his evidence, and he must, in replying, call in the internal sense, and I can then show him that this sense, or cognitive power (for it is not a sense except in an abusive application of the term), declares that we know a something, or thing with a positive existence. This is a knowledge which cannot be explained, nor defined in the sense of being resolved into anything simpler or founded on anything deeper. It is a simple element implied in every intelligent act, and not derived from any other act or exercise. It is a basis on which other knowledge may be reared, and not a superstructure standing on another foundation. As it is a primitive, so it is a necessary conviction. We cannot by any other supposed knowledge undermine or set aside this fundamental knowledge. We cannot be made by any process of speculation or ratiocination to believe that we have not being. The process of reason- ing which would set aside this cognition can plead no principle stronger than the conviction which we have in favour of the reality of self. In saying that we know self as possessed of being, we do not mean to affirm that we know all about self, or about our spiritual nature. There are mysteries about self, and about everything else we know, sufficient to awe every truly wise man into humility. All that is meant is, that, whatever may be unknown, we always know unser eigenes Subject nur als Erscheinung, nicbt aber nacb dem, vras es an sicb selbst ist, erkennen” (ib. p. 850). Mr. Mansel has done great service to philosophy by maintaining so clearly and resolutely, in his ‘Prolegomena Logica,’ and the article on ‘Metaphysics’ in the ‘Ency- clopaedia Britannica,’ that we intuitively know self. “I am imme- diately conscious of myself seeing and hearing, willing and thinking” (Prol. Log. p. 129). Hamilton speaks of our being conscious every moment of our existence, and of the ego as a “ self-subsistent entity” (Metaph. Lect. 19). SPIRIT. 151 being whenever we know any of the objects presented to us from within or from without. This subject will be resumed in a more special manner in next Chapter. II. We know self as not depending for its existence on our observation of it. Of course we can know self only when we know self; our knowledge of self exists not till we have the knowledge, and it exists only so long as we have the knowledge. But when we come to know self, we know it as already existing, and we do not look on its continued existence as depending on our recogni- tion of it. III. We know self as being in itself an abiding exist- ence. Not that we are to stretch this conviction so far as to believe in the self-existence of mind, or in its eter- nal existence. We believe certainly in the permanence of mind independent of our cognition of it, and amidst all the shiftings and variations of its states. Yet this does not imply that there never was a time when self was non-existing. For aught this conviction says, there may have been a time when self came into existence—another conviction assures us that when it did, it must have had a cause. It must be added that this conviction does not go the length of assuring us that mind must exist for ever, or that it must exist after the dissolution of the body. It does indeed seem to say that, if it shall cease to exist, it must be in virtue of some cause adequate to destroy it; and it helps to produce and strengthen the feeling which the dying man cherishes when he looks on the soul as likely to abide when the body is dead. But as to whether the dissolution of the bodily frame is a sufficient cause of the decease of the soul,—as to whether it may abide when the bodily frame is disorganized,—this is a question to be settled not altogether by intuition, but by a number of other considerations, and more particu- larly by the conviction that God will call us into judg- 152 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. ment at last, and is most definitely settled, after all, by the inspired declarations of the Word of God. But it is pleasant to observe that there is an original conviction altogether in unison with this derivative belief, a convic- tion leading us to look on self as permanent unless there be a cause working adequate to its dissolution. According to the views presented under these heads, the existence of self is a position to be assumed, and not to be proven. It does not need proof, and no proof should be offered; no mediate evidence could possibly be clearer than the truth which it is brought to support. It has been keenly disputed how we are to understand the “ Cogito, ergo sum,” of Descartes. Are we to regard it as a process of reasoning ? If it be so, it is either a pe- titio principii, or its conclusiveness may be doubted. If the cogito be understood as embracing ego, that is, be understood as ego cogito, then the ego is evidently in- volved in it, is in fact assumed. If it means anything short of this, then it might be difficult to establish the accuracy of the inference; "thus, if the cogito does not embrace the ego, it is not clear that the conclusion fol- lows.* Or are we to regard the statement as a sort of primitive judgment, not implying mediate reasoning or a middle termpf Taken in this sense, I would reckon that the connection between thought and existence is in- volved in our knowledge of self as existing, rather than that the knowledge of self issues from the perception of the connection between thought and personal existence. Or are we to look on the expression as simply a mode of * Kant lias a powerful criticism of tlie “ Cogito, ergo sum,” considered as an argument, in his Paralogismen d. r. Vern. in the Kritik. t In answering the objections of Gassendi, Descartes says: “ Cum advertimus nos esse res cogitantes, prima qusedam notio est quae et nullo syllogismo concluditur; neque etiam quis dicit ‘ Ego cogito, ergo sum, sive existo,’ existentiam ex cogitatione per syllogismum deducit, sed tanquam rem per se notam simpliei mentis intuitu agnoscit.” See the subj ect discussed by Cousin, Prem. Ser. tom. i. let?, vi. SPIRIT. 153 stating an assumption ? In this case the word ergo, the usual symbol of reasoning, comes in awkwardly; and besides, the truth to be assumed is not the complex judgment, cogito, ergo sum, but the fact revealed at once to consciousness of ego cogitans.* This primitive cog- nition may be the ground of a number of judgments, but it is to reverse the order of things entirely to make any one of these judgments the ground of the cognitions. The cognitions which have been unfolded in this Chap- ter, form, when memory begins to be exercised, the ground of our recognition of our personal identity, and lead us to believe in a self which abideth amid all changes of thought and mood and feeling. This subject will be resumed by us under the head of Primitive Judgments. IV. We know self as exercising potency. We have seen that we know it as having being; we know it further as having active being. We know it as acting, we know it as being acted on, we know it as the source of action.f Even in sense-perception we know it as being acted on from without,—nay, we know it as itself acting in producing the result. So far as we know ob- jects acting on it, we know it as capable of being in- fluenced,—in other words, as having a capacity of a particular description. So far as we know it acting in producing changes in itself or other things, we know it * “ C’est par une meme perception de notre ame qne nous eprouvons le sentiment intime et de notre pensee et de notre existence” (Buffier, Prem. Ver. p. i. c. i.). t Sir W. Hamilton admits all I am pleading for. “ I know myself as a force in energy, the not-self as a counter-force in energy” (Note D, p. 666, of Ap. to Reid). And again: “We have a perception proper, of the secundo-primary quality, of resistance in an extra-organic force as an immediate cognition” (p. 883). Is this statement an essential part of his doctrine, or an incidental admission P If part of his system, it should modify the view he has given elsewhere of our conviction of power as being a mere impotency (see Appendix to Discuss.). If it be inadvertent, it is a proof that truth will come out of honest men, in spite of the errors of their system. 154 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. as a potency, as having power. When we recollect, when we fondly dwell on a particular scene, when we fix the thoughts on a particular object, we are exercising power, and by consciousness we know that we are doing so. When in consequence of coming to know of events bearing upon us personally,—say of some blessing about to descend, or calamity about to befall,—we rejoice or grieve, we experience an effect. This conscious potency is especially felt in all exercises of the will, whether it be directed to the mental action which we wish to stay or quicken, or the bodily organism which we purpose to move. I demur, indeed, to the view maintained by some philosophers of eminence, that our idea of power is obtained exclusively from the consciousness of the power of will over the muscles. But I am persuaded that our most vivid conviction of power is derived from the influence of the will both on bodily and mental ac- tion,* and that the influence of the will on the organism is what enables us to connect mental with bodily action. But here it will be necessary to offer an explanation to save ourselves from obvious difficulties, which many have not seen their way to overcome. We shall find, under another head, that while we believe intuitively that every effect has a cause, we do not know by intuition what the cause is apart from experience; and that while we are convinced that the cause produces the effect, it is only by experience we know what the effect is. It follows that we do not know intuitively what or how many * This is substantially the view of Locke, wbo says, “ Bodies by our senses do not afford us so clear and distinct an idea of active power as we bave from reflection on the operations of our own mind.” In de- riving our idea of Power from Sensation and Reflection, he supposes the mind to be actively and intelligently exercised. “ Whatever change is observed, the mind must collect a power somewhere to make that change” (Essay, ii. xxi. 4). But Locke has omitted to inquire what it is in the mind which insists that it must collect a cause wherever there is a change. SPIRIT. 155 powers must concur to produce a given effect. This qualification will be found to have a great significance imparted to it by the circumstance to be afterwards noticed, that in order to most creature effects there is need of a concurrence of causes, or of a concause. When I will to move my arm, I know that the will is one of the elements in producing the effect, but I do not know, till physiology tells me, how many others must co-operate. It follows that one of the elements of a complex cause may act and no effect follow, because one part of the con- cause is absent. I may will to take a cheerful view of every- thing, and yet not be able owing to the rise of gloomy thoughts. I may will to move my arm and yet the arm may not move, because paralysis has cut off the concur- rence of the organism. This subject will again come before us under various aspects. Y. We know the knowing mind to be different from the material object known, whether this be the organism as affected or the object affecting it. Not that we know by intuition wherein the difference lies; not that we are in a position to say whether they may not, after all, have points of resemblance, and a mutual dependence, and a reciprocal influence,—on these points our only guide is a gathered experience. But in every act in which we know a bodily object, we know it to be dif- ferent from self, and self to be different from it. This is a conviction which we can never lose, and of which no sophistry can deprive us. We carry it with us at all times, and wherever we go. It makes it impossible for any man to confound himself with the universe, or the universe with him. Man may mistake one external ob- ject for another, but it is not possible that he should mistake an external object for himself, or identify himself with any other object. This conviction is thus a means, as shall be shown later in the treatise, of delivering us 15G PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. from the more common forms of idealism, and from every form of pantheism. VI. We know self in every one of its states, as these pass before self-consciousness. And herein lies an im- portant difference between the knowledge we have of mind and the greater portion of the knowledge we have acquired of the material universe. The knowledge which we have of matter by intuition is extremely limited. What we thus know, indeed, is supremely valuable, as the ground on which we erect all our other information; still it is in itself very narrow, being confined to an ac- quaintance with our organism as extended and as ex- ercising an influence on the mind, and to objects imme- diately in contact with it. Most even of the knowledge which we have of our organism, and of objects in contact with it, is derivative; and there is a process of inference in all that we know of objects at a distance,—of sun, moon, stars, of hills, rivers, valleys,—and of the persons and countenances and conversations of our friends. But in regard to our own minds, we know all the individual facts directly and intuitively. We gaze at once on the mind thinking, imagining, feeling, resolving. In this view it may be safely said that we know more of certain of the states and of the action of mind than we know of the whole material universe, even in this age of advanced science. It should be added, in order to save the remark from appearing to some incredibly extravagant, that while we thus know spontaneously so much about the workings of the mind, the majority of men think far more about their objective than their subjective knowledge. It should be further added, that while we are ever growing, more than people who have not thought on the subject imagine, in the knowledge of our mental affections, yet there are greater difficulties in adding to our original stock in the mental than in the material world. ANALYSIS OF OUR PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. 157 It is the office of psychology, as a science, to observe wherein the states of mind which fall under conscious- ness agree and wherein they differ, and to endeavour to arrange and classify them. In conducting this its work, all the facts are discovered by consciousness as an intuitive faculty. Our sensations, our perceptions, our elaborated thoughts, our moral cognitions, our emotions, our wishes, our volitions, and all our necessary convictions, are under our immediate view. But it is to be carefully observed that the classification is a work of discursive, and not of intuitive thought. We know our thoughts and feelings, but not as thoughts or feelings. As to how we are to arrange them, and as to what is the best classification of our mental states, this is a question not for intuition, but for mental science, looking to the facts which conscious- ness makes known. We are conscious, not of faculties, but merely of individual energies, which we compare and arrange under certain heads as faculties. It is impor- tant to state here once more that we are conscious of the intuitions of the mind as individual energies, and not as abstract forms or general laws. CHAPTER II. ANALYSIS OF OUR PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. Sect. I, (Preliminary.) On the Nature oe Abstraction and Generalization. As abstraction and generalization perform so important a part in the formation of tbe a priori notions and maxims out of tbe concrete and individual convictions, it will be necessary to explain the nature of these processes, the more so as a defective account has often been given of them. 158 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. It is very generally acknowledged that man’s mind begins with the concrete, and thence reaches the abstract, that is, that it first knows or contemplates an object with the qualities presenting themselves, and that it afterwards learns to consider the object apart from any particular quality, or the quality apart from the object. The statement now made, does not imply that man’s pri- mary knowledge is complex. The complex is not the same as the concrete. In complex knowledge man has mingled several cogni- tions which are simple; but to man the concrete is the simple. His primary knowledge is of objects with certain qualities which he may subsequently he able to separate and distinguish. Thus by the eye he gets a knowledge of the bodies before him as at one and the same time extended and coloured. By the muscular sense, or locomotive energy, he knows objects as extended, movable, and resisting energy. It is a curious circumstance that when the me- mory recalls an object, it always presents it in the concrete, that is, with qualities which can be separated. We cannot even ima- gine an object except in the concrete ; we cannot picture to our- selves an extended surface without giving it colour of some kind, and we cannot imagine a colour except on an extended surface. With this primary knowledge and these representations in pos- session, the mind proceeds to abstract, and is urged to do so by a native intellectual impulse. It can separate in thought the quali- ties from the object, or one quality from another, say the colour from the form. Abstraction may be considered in a wider or in a narrower sense. It may be regarded, in an extended sense, as that opera- tion of mind, in which, to use the language of Whately, “ we draw off and contemplate separately any part of an object presented to the mind, disregarding the rest” (Logic Anal. Out.). In this more general sense the parts may exist separately as well as the whole; thus, having seen a judge with his wig, we can not only separate in thought the wig from the judge, but the wig can in fact be separated from the wearer. In a narrower sense, abstrac- tion is that operation of mind in which we contemplate the quality of an object separately from the object. “An abstract name,” says Mr. Mill (Logic, b. i. c. ii.), “ is a name which stands for an attri- bute of a thing.” In this sense the part separated in thought can- not be separated from the object in fact. Colour may be thought of (not seen or imagined) apart from an extended body, but cannot exist apart from a coloured object. It is a very common impression that our abstractions are in no sense realities. I wish at this early stage of the investigations to ANALYSIS OF OUR PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. 159 be prosecuted in this treatise, to set myself against this view, which has sometimes been positively expressed, but is far more fre- quently underlying and implied in statements and arguments without being formally announced. I lay down a very different position, that if the concrete be real, and the abstraction be pro- perly made, the abstract thing, that is, the thing contemplated in the abstraction, will also be real. I may never have seen a bird without wings, but I can consider the wings apart from the bird, and I am sure that the wings have as real an existence as the bird itself. This will be admitted at once in regard to all such cases as this, in which I can in fact separate the pinions from the body of the fowl. But I go a step further, and maintain, that even in cases in which the part abstracted cannot be separated in reality from the whole, still it is to be considered as real. It may not have, or be capable of having, an independent reality, but still it has a re- ality. I can think of gravitation apart from a given body, or from the chemical affinity of that body; and in doing so I do not sup- pose that it can exist apart from body ; still the gravitation has an existence just as much as the body has, it has not a reality inde- pendent of the body, but it has a reality in the body, as a quality of it. The same remark might be applied to, and will hold good of, any other abstraction. No doubt if the original concrete object be imaginary, the abstraction formed from it may be the same ; I can separate in thought the beauty of Venus from Venus herself; and of course, as Venus is ideal, so also is her beauty. But when the object is real, and I abstract or separately contemplate what has been known in the real, then, as the concrete object is real, so is also the part or quality abstracted real; not that it may be a real- ity capable of subsisting in itself, but still a reality in the object as a quality of it. I reckon it of the utmost moment to make this remark. The view here presented saves us on the one hand from an extreme Eealism, which would attribute an independent reality to every quality abstracted, which would for example represent beauty as a separate thing, like a beautiful scene in nature, and on the other hand, from what is more important in our present inquiry, from regarding it as a nonentity, or at the utmost as a mere form or cre- ation of the mind.* We are ever hearing the phrase repeated a * “ Concreta vere res sint, abstracta non sunt res sed rerum modi; modi autem nibil aliud sunt quam relationes rei ad intellectual seu appa- rendi facultates” (Leibnitz de Stilo Pbilos.: Nizolii Op. p. 63). In this as in other matters, Leibnitz introduced a subjective tendency,which came forth in full manifestation only in a later age. 160 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. “ mere abstraction; ” and the language is applied to such objects as space, time, beauty, and even truth and moral good. In opposi- tion to such views, I maintain that abstraction is not necessarily concerned about fictions or illusions. Abstractions are not, as they have often been represented, the attenuated ghosts of de- parted quantities ; they may rather be represented as the very skeleton of the body, not capable of action alone, but still an im- portant existence in the btfdy, acting with its covering of flesh and skin. Abstraction is not only a lofty intellectual exercise, it is in a sense a cognitive act, and when the concrete object looked at is real, it will give us, if properly conducted, a reality in the part se- parated. As to whether this part is or is not capable of a sepa- rate existence, this depends on the nature of the original concrete cognition. Generalization is dependent on abstraction, and arises out of it. In generalization we contemplate an indefinite number of objects as possessing a common attribute or attributes. A general notion is a notion of these objects. This expressed in language is a com- mon term, which therefore stands for an indefinite number of ob- jects, for all that possess the common quality or qualities. As abstractions are formed out of concretes, so generalizations are formed out of individuals or singulars. It has been very generally allowed by philosophers that the mind begins with the knowledge of individual objects or scenes presented to it. Among these objects it may, by its comparative faculty, discover resem- blances. In some cases the comparison is preceded by an ab- straction of the qualities in respect of which the objects are alike; in other cases it may be perceived at once that there is a resem- blance, and the abstraction of the points of resemblance may follow. In all cases, both the discovery of resemblance and ab- straction are needful to generalization, in which we put in a class, and usually call by a common name, the objects thought to re- semble each other in certain respects, and so far as they resemble each other. 1 am prepared to lay down in regard to generalization a pro- position similar to that which I am inclined to enforce in regard to abstraction. When the individuals are real, the generaliza- tion has also a reality; that is, there is a reality in the class. True, I may constitute a class from imaginary individuals,—say a class of griffins, or a class of mermaids, or a class of ghosts. In such a case the general is as unreal as the singular. But if my generalization is from real objects; if it is a generalization made of objects in nature, say of marbles, or reptiles, or cruciferous ANALYSIS OF OUR PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. 161 plants, or even of objects of human workmanship, such as chairs, or houses, or churches, then the intellectual product has also a reality involved. I do not mean to say that the general exists, or can exist, as an individual thing, like the singulars which it em- braces,—that the class crocodile has the same sort of existence as the individual crocodile,—but I maintain that it has a reality in the common attributes possessed by the objects. In abstraction, the reality may be simply that of an attribute in an individual object. In generalization, it is the possession of a common attribute by an indefinite number of objects. The com- position of marble is a fact quite as much, though not exactly of the same sort, as the limestone itself. The possession of cold blood, and of the three heart-compartments, is a reality quite as much as the individual crocodile is. The possession of four cross petals is a real thing, just as a particular wild mustard-plant is. The structure and adaptation to a practical use of chair, house, and church, are not fictitious any more than this chair, or this house, or this church is. This account preserves us on the one hand from an extravagant realism, which would give to the universal the same sort of reality as the singular; and on the other, from an extreme conceptualism or nominalism, which would place the reality solely in the conception of the mind, or in the name. The class has a reality, hut it is simply in the possession of common qualities by an indefinite number of objects. According to this view, abstraction and generalization are pro- cesses of a very high order; they are, in fact, essential to philoso- phy, quite as much so, indeed, as Plato and the Schoolmen supposed; without them we can never reach the truths on which the higher forms of wisdom gaze. They always pre-suppose, indeed, that something has been given them ; but, acting upon this, they turn it to most important purposes, and if they start with realities and are properly conducted, they are ever in the region of realities, and of realities of the highest kind. We shall see as we advance that all philosophic notions and maxims are the results of these processes, some of them being abstractions, and others being also of the nature of generalizations. Sect. II. On Being. But what can be said of Being? Verily, little can be said of it. The mistake of metaphysicians lies in their saying too much; and they have made assertions which have, and can have, no meaning, and landed themselves 162 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. in self-created mysteries or in contradictions. So little can be affirmed of Being, not because of the complexity of the idea, but because of its simplicity; we can find nothing simpler into which to resolve it. We have come to ultimate truth, and there is really no deeper foundation on which to rest it. There is no light behind in which to show it in vivid outline. In the concrete every one has the cognition of Being, just as every man has a skeleton in his frame. But the common mind is apt to turn away from the abstract idea, as it does from an anatomical preparation; or ra- ther, it feels as if such attenuated notions belong to the regions of ghosts, where “ Entity and quiddity, The ghosts of defunct bodies, fly.” All that the metaphysician can do is to appeal to the perception which all men form, to separate this from the others with which it is joined, and make it stand out singly and simply, that it may shine and be seen in its own light, and with this the mind will be satisfied:— “ Who thinks of asking if the sun is light, Observing that it lightens ?” Those who attempt anything more, and to peer into the object, will find that the light darkens as they gaze upon it. “ When I burned in desire to question them further, they made themselves—air, into which they va- nished.” I allow that the abstract notion of Being is one which the mind is not inclined spontaneously to fashion. As to many other abstractions, it is led naturally to form them; they are framed for it, or it is compelled by the circumstances in which it is placed to frame them. Thus I see a man with a black coat one day, and with a grey coat the next, and I cannot but separate the colour from ANALYSIS OF OUR PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. 163 the object. But in such high abstractions as Being, that which we contemplate is never, in fact, separated from any one thing. Still Being is an abstraction which we are constrained to make for philosophic purposes, and it was, in fact, formed so early as the age of the specu- lators of the Eleatic School. It is the one thing to be found objectively in all our knowledge. Hence in all our abstractions it is that which remains; in the ascending process of generalization it is the summum genus. This does not prove that Being can exist apart from a special mode of existence, or the exercise of some quality. Nor does it prove that we can know Being se- parate from a concrete existence. I hold the one as well as the other of these to be impossible. But in all know- ledge we know what we know as having existence, which is Being. I cannot give my adhesion to the opinion of those who speak so strongly of man being incapacitated to know Being. I have already intimated my dissent from the Kantian doctrine that we do not know things, but ap- pearances ; and even from the theory of those Scottish metaphysicians who affirm that we do not know things, but qualities. What we know is the thing manifesting itself to us,—is the thing exercising particular qualities. But then it is confidently asserted that we do not know the “ thing in itself.” The language, I rather think, is unmeaning; but if it has a meaning, it is incorrect. I do not believe that there is any such thing in existence as Being in itself, or that man can even so much as imagine it: and if this be so, it is clear that we cannot know it, and desirable that we should not suppose that we know it. Of this I am sure, that those Neo-Pla- tonists who professed to be able to rise to the discovery of Being in itself (which could only be the abstract idea of Being), and to be employed in gazing on it, had 164 PRIMITIVE COGNITIONS. miserably bare and most unprofitable matter of medi- tation, whether for intellectual, or moral, or religious ends. But if any mean to deny that we can know Being as it is, I maintain in opposition to them, and I appeal to consciousness to confirm me when I say, that we immediately know Being in every act of cognition. But then we are told that we cannot know the mystery of Being.* I am under a strong impression that specu- lators have attached a much greater amount of mystery to this simple subject than really belongs to it. Of this I am sure, that much of the obscurity which has col- lected around it has sprung from the confused discus- sions of metaphysicians, who have laboured to explain what needs no explanation to our intelligence, or to get a basis on which to build what stands securely on its own foundation. I do indeed most fully admit that there may be much about Being which we do not know; much about Being generally, much about every indi- vidual Being, unknown to us and unknowable in this world. Still I do affirm that we know so much of Being, and that any further knowledge conveyed to us would not set aside our present knowledge, but would simply enlarge it. Sect. III. On Substance. All that the metaphysician can do in regard to sub- * Kant everywhere speaks of our not knowing the “ Ding an sich.” See in the Kritik of Pure Reason (Antin. d. r. Y. Abs. vi.). M. Cousin allows to Kant that we have not a consciousness of our proper nature, otherwise, he says, that the abysses and mysteries of existence would all be known; but to save himself from the Kantian consequences, he calls in reason to give us a conviction of self and personal identity :— “ Nul de nous n’a conscience de sa propre nature, sans quoi les abimes de l’existence seraient faciles a sonder, les mysteres de lame nous seraient parfaitement connus.” “ L’identite personnelle est une con- viction de la raison ” (ser. ii. le