HAECKELS -::(|fnfsis of iDan. -BV Lester F. Ward, A. M. EDWARD STERN & CO., 125 and 127 North Seventh Street.-^ HAECKEL’S GENESIS OF lAN = OR = Pistroj of tljc tlfl’i'lopnunt of t|c |)uman llittt. BEING A REVIEW OF HIS “ANTHROPOGENIE,” AND EMBRACING A SUMMARY EXPOSITION OF HIS VIEWS AND OF THOSE OF THE ADVANCED GERMAN SCHOOL OF SCIENCE. BY LESTER F. WARD, A.M. EDWARD STERN & CO. Philadelphia: r2j c° 127 North Seventh St. Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1879, by EDWARD STERN & CO., In the Office of the Librarian of Congress, at Washington, D. C. PRESS OF EDWARD STERN & CO., 125 & 127 NORTH SEVENTH STREET, PHILA. PREFACE. 'T'HE three papers constituting this little brochure were originally J. contributed to the Penn Monthly, and appeared in the April, May, and July numbers of that magazine for 1877. As the work which it was their more especial object to review has not yet been placed before the non-German reading public, no apology is offered for their reproduction in separate form. In view, however, of the popular interest which the views of Prof. Haeckel have since called forth, and which seems to be still increasing, it was thought an opportune moment for laying before the general public this condensed exposition of the thought and labors of the great naturalist and philosopher. It may further interest the reader to learn that Prof. Haeckel has acknowledged, in a private communication to the author, the substantial correctness with which these papers represent his position. L. F. W. Washington, March, 18yp. HAECKEL’S GENESIS OF MAN, OR HISTORY OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE HUMAN RACE.1 I. GENERAL HISTORY OF THE DOCTRINE OF DESCENT. IT is no derogation from the epoch-making labors of Charles Darwin to admit that the arguments he has presented in sup- port of his celebrated theory constitute, as it were, but the half of the vast array which the present state of biological science is capable of marshalling in its defence. The sources from which the evidences of descent and natural selection must be derived, may be divided into two general classes: First, Paleontology, Comparative Anatomy and Osteology, and Geographical Distribution (Chorology), i. e., a comparison of the adult forms of animals both living and fossil (.Phytogeny); and Second, the study of embryonic changes and post-natal metamor- phoses, or a comparison of undeveloped animal forms (Ontogeny). Of these two classes it may be said that the first have been fur- nished by Darwin, the second by Haeckel. Not that Darwin, either in his Origin of Species or in his Descent of Man, has wholly ignored the bearing of embryological considerations upon his theory. In the former work he has devoted seventeen pages of one of his concluding chapters to “ Development and Embry- ology ; ” the greater part of which, however, is occupied in pointing out the importance of the various kinds of metamorphosis, chiefly as it is observed in insects, amphibians, etc., after birth ; only inci- dentally referring to those more obscure metamorphoses which take place within the egg or the uterus. He does allude, however, more directly to Von Baer’s law, but without designating it as such ; and contents himself with quoting the passage, cited also by Haeckel in the preface to the third edi- tion of his History of Creation (1870), in which the great Russian embryologist remarks upon the striking similarity of many em- 1 Anthropogenic, oder Entwickelungsgeschichte des Menschen, von Ernst Haeckel, Professor an der Universitat Jena. Leipsic, 1874. 6 GENESIS OF MAN. bryos, so much so that he was quite unable to say to what animals two specimens which he had preserved in alcohol but had neglected to label, really belonged. Still less attention has Darwin paid to this source of argument in his Descent of Man. A few lines quoted from Von Baer and from Huxley, on page 14 of Vol. I, a figure of the embryo of a human being and one of a dog, from Ecker, on page 15, with brief comments, disposes of this branch of his great argument. Almost as much had been said by the author of the Vestiges of Creation, in 1842.2 It is safe, therefore, to assume that at the time of the appearance of the Origin of Species (1859), Darwin had no conception of the real part that the arguments from embiyology were destined to play in establishing his doctrine of the development of organic forms. And although in subse- quent editions he was able to notice the Gcnerelle Morphologic, it is still improbable that even then he had any adequate idea of the powerful ally he was to have in Germany, as the Naturliche Scliopf- ungsgeschichte, and not less the work under review, have proved the professor of Jena to be. It is of the former of these works that Darwin says that if it had appeared before the Descent of Man had been written, he would probably never have completed the latter. Professor Haeckel is no mere disciple of Darwin, profound as is his admiration of him, and unreserved as is his expression of that admiration. His own countrymen have accused him of being “ more Darwinistic than Darwin himself,” but it is clear that a large part of this difference is in.kind rather than in degree, and that he has infused into the developmental philosophy a true Haeckelian element. It is true that he drew the logical conclusion from the premises furnished by the Origin of Species five years be- fore the announcement of its recognition by Darwin himself in his Descent of Man. This conclusion he boldly and forcibly enunci- ated in the introduction to his Genercllc Morphologic, published in 1866, and reiterated with still greater emphasis in his Naturliche ScHopfungsgcschichtc, in 1868. Between this period and that of the appearance of the Descent of Man, Haeckel was exposed to the bitterest attacks, not only from the adherents of the Church and the opponents of Darwin generally, but from those adherents of Darwinism in Germany—and they were many—whose conception 2 New York, 1845, ?• Is°- GENESIS OF MAN. 7 of it was limited to the body of principles contained in the Origin of Species. As in that work all reference to the position of the human race in the animal kingdom was carefully excluded, thus ingeniously avoiding the shock of prejudice which any such con- nection would have occasioned, the simplicity, the naivete, and, at the same time, the force of reasoning displayed in it, not only won the immediate assent of all fully emancipated minds, but took a strong hold upon great numbers of liberally educated per- sons whose independent reflections had not yet carried them wholly out from under the influence of theological conceptions. Among these were many thoroughly scientific men and naturalists, special- ists in the various departments of science, whose analytical labors had not left them time fora synthesis of the facts even within their own special branch of research. These accepted the conclusions drawn in the Origin of Species without perceiving that other and important ones might and must follow from the same premises. And because Haeckel drew these logical and necessary conclu- sions, these persons attacked him from all sides, and heaped upon him every form of accusation. Besides the charge above referred to of out-Darwining Darwin, and of going further than Darwin him- self would ever sanction, there was added the stronger one that Haeckel knew nothing about true Darwinism. The appearance in 1871 of Darwin’s Descent of Man placed these anti-Haeckel Dar- winians in a most embarrassing situation, silencing many, convert- ing numbers, and driving not a few into the theological camp. But Haeckel emerged majestically from the battle, unscathed and undaunted. To charges of “ radicalism ” he had simply replied : “ Radical thinking is consistent thinking, which allows itself to be checked by no barriers of tradition or of enforced dogma.” To the confused outcry of the theological school and of the anti-Dar- winians in general, he did not deem it worth his while to reply. A satirical remark upon this class, however, is worth reproducing and might be ranked alongside of Darwin’s cutting sarcasm, wherein he says that he who scorns to be descended from a beast will generally reveal his descent in the act of sneering, whereby he will expose his canine teeth. “Itis an interesting and instructive circumstance,” says Haeckel, “that just those persons are most shocked and indignant at the discovery of the natural development of the human race from the apes, who, in their intellectual develop- 8 GENESIS OF MAN. ment and cerebral differentiation, are obviously least removed from our common tertiary ancestors.” Both in his History of Creation and in his Ant]iropogeny, Haeckel has done a service to the cause of evolution by reviewing, in a fair and disinterested manner, the history of the origin and progress of those ideas which have culminated in the Darwinian theory. Let us glance for a moment at this history. Passing over the names of Wolff, Baer, Kant, Schleiden, Oken, and Humboldt, in Germany, of Buffon and Geoffrey St. Hilaire, in France, and of Dean Herbert, Professor Grant, Patrick Matthew, Freke, and Herbert Spencer (Essays, 1852), in England, all of whom had given more or less definite expression to these pro- gressive ideas prior to the appearance of the Origin of Species, it may be remarked that the great conception of the natural relation- ship (filiation) of all organic forms and their descent or development from common ancestors that have existed in more or less remote periods of the past, had a threefold independent origin in the minds of three men who were contemporary at the close of the last and the beginning of the present century, in each of the three great nations that now lead the intellectual world. These men were Erasmus Darwin, grandfather of the illustrious Charles, in Eng- land, Wolfgang Goethe, the great poet and philosopher, in Germany, and Jean Lamarck, in France. Wholly unacquainted with each other and with each other’s works, these three men, almost at the same time, gave utterance to substantially the same fundamental ideas, and elaborated in more or less extended and systematic form the essential ground-principles which now underlie the edifice of all progressive biological science. In his work entitled Zdonomia, published in 1794, Erasmus Darwin lays great weight upon the transformation of species of animals and plants through their own activities of life and through forced habituation to changed conditions of existence. It is a current remark, as applied to Charles Darwin, that he fur- nishes in himself one of the finest illustrations of “ development,” and thus of the truth of his own theory, that can be cited. Far more pointed, however, is the pleasantry of Haeckel, when, refer- ring to the grandfather of Charles as entertaining the germs of his grandson’s philosophy, and noting the striking circumstance that his father, though a respectable physician, exhibited no signs GENESIS OF MAN. 9 of having inherited these intellectual characteristics, he cites the case as a good example of “ atavism,” and remarks that “ Erasmus Darwin transmitted, according to the law of latent inheritance, de- finite molecular motions in the ganglion cells of his cerebrum to his grandson Charles without their manifesting themselves in his son Robert.” The importance of Erasmus Darwin’s views, however, mixed as they were with some vagaries and unbalanced speculations, was slight as compared with that which we must ascribe to those of Goethe. In his various essays and writings on “ Natural Science ” in general (1780), on Comparative Anatomy and Osteology (1786), on the Metamorphoses of Plants (1790), and in later works, he has wrought out a philosophy of organic life, which, when carefully analyzed and translated into the terminology now adopted, is found to contain, in their most general and fundamental form, the essen- tial principles of the Darwinian theory of development. A few passages wall illustrate this. In 1706 he wrote; “All the more perfect organic natures, under which we see fishes, amphib- ians, birds, mammals, and, at the head of these last, man, are formed according to one original type (Urbild), which in its dura- ble parts only deviates more or less, and is still daily being im- proved and transformed through propagation.” It is from this and other passages in which Goethe establishes his doctrine of an origi- nal type or image, which varies only slightly and in detail and not in plan, that the modern adherents of the theory of fixed types seem to have derived their chief arguments. Cuvier must have been con- versant with Goethe’s scientific writings, and he may have drawn largely upon them in founding his celebrated system of classifica- tion. But like some other great works that have become author- ity, those of Goethe are found, in some things, to admit of two in- terpretations, and to supply texts looking more than one way. The above passage, taken in connection with others, is now seen still more clearly to give countenance to what is now the powerful rival of the doctrine of types : viz., the doctrine of descent. In another place he says : “An internal original community (Gemcinschaft) lies at the bottom of all organization ; difference of form, on the contrary, arises from the necessary relations to the external world, and we may, therefore, with right assume an original, simultaneous varia- tion and an incessantly progressive transformation, in order to com- prehend the at once constant and deviating phenomena.” GENESIS OF MAN. To further explain this paradox he assumes two independent forces or impulses, working harmoniously together in nature, an internal formative impulse {innercr Bildungstrieb), and an external formative impulse (dussever Bildungstrieb). The former of these he also, in different passages, designates as the specific force (Specified- tionstrieb) and as the centripetal force ; the latter, on the other hand, he calls the modifying force or impulse of variation (Variationstrieb, and the centrifugal force. He also uses the term metamorphosis in a general (phylogenetic) sense as applied to the changes that take place in species and genera rather than in individuals. The following passage contains the kernel of this entire portion of his philosophy: “ The idea of metamorphosis is like that of the vis centrifuga, and would lose itself in infinity were there not a check offered to it; this check is the specific force (Specificationstrieb), the stubborn power of permanency {sake Bcharrlichkcitsvermbgen) of whatever has once become a reality, a vis centripeta, which in its deepest foundations can possess no externality.” If, now, we translate Goethe’s internal formative impulse, specific force, or centripetal force, by the modern term heredity, as we un- doubtedly may, and his external formative impulse, modifying force, or centrifugal force, by the modern term adaptation, as we may still more clearly do, we shall have, m Goethe’s philosophy of life, neither more nor less than the essential elements of the modern doctrine of descent. Of course, nothing is here found but the general principles ; the mode and the examples could not have been furnished in Germany when Goethe wrote. Haeckel, however, is abundantly justified in pointing to Ger- many’s greatest genius as having long ago given utterance to the most radical of his own doctrines and that for which he has re- ceived the severest animadversions, when, in the passage first quoted, he places man at the head of the mammalian class. And yet, who had thought of assailing Goethe with the charge of deriv- ing man from the apes ! With almost equal justice does Haeckel claim that, in the follow- ing and other passages, Goethe has not only declared the genea- logical relationship of the vegetable to the animal kingdom, but has furnished the nucleus of the unitary or monophyletic theory of descent. “ When we consider plants and animals in their most im- GENESIS OF MAN. 11 perfect condition they are scarcely to be distinguished. This much, however, we may say, that those creatures that now and then ap- appear, having relationships with plants and with animals difficult to separate, perfect themselves in two opposite directions, so that the plant at last glorifies itself in the tree, durable and fixed, the animal, in man, with the highest degree of mobility and freedom.” The ambiguity of Goethe’s language is due to the profundity and high generality of his ideas, coupled with a certain poetic vagueness so indispensable to his genius. In the former quality, though not at all in the latter, one is reminded of that profound and comprehensive analysis which, with all the materials of that later date (1866), and with the power of logic characteristic of England’s foremost philosopher, Herbert Spencer, in his Biology, (vol. 1, ch. xi., and xii.), has made of these same principles; a treatise, I may add, which Haeckel has indeed recognized,3 but upon which he could scarcely have failed to place more emphasis if he had been thoroughly acquainted with it. Quite different in method and character from Goethe’s contribu- tion to the theory of transmutation and descent was that of La- marck. Whatever his philosophy may have lacked in profundity, it was not open to the charge of ambiguity. All its shortcomings were amply compensated for by the wealth of illustration and the multiplicity of facts drawn directly from nature, which, as a life- long naturalist, he was able to bring to its support. In this respect (and this is after all the chief consideration), the now celebrated, though long neglected, Philosophic Zoologique is alone, of all the works that had preceded it or were contemporary with it, worthy of a serious comparison with the Origin of Species or the Descent of Man. And it is certainly a remarkable coincidence and may have for some readers, if no other, at least a mnemonic value, that the Philosophic Zoologique and the Origin of Species were separated by the space of just half a century, the former appearing in 1809, the latter in 1859. The interest of this circumstance is still further heightened by the fact that Charles Darwin 'was born in the year 1809, the same in which the great precursor of his own works like- wise issued into the world ; as if its subtle influence had wafted across the channel and breathed its mysterious afflatus into the nostrils of the new-born herald of its principles! 3 Schopfungsgeschichte, 5 Aufl. pp. 106, 657. 12 GENESIS OF MAN. The dim intimations and scattered glimpses of Goethe and ot Dr. Darwin were insignificant in comparison with the lucid illus- trations and systematic arguments of the great French naturalist. After so many years of assiduous study Lamarck, as it were, but copied his conclusions from the pages of nature where facts stood forth like letters in a book. Yet none the less credit to his intel- lect, for was not this same book sealed to his great contem- porary, Cuvier, who knew its alphabet equally well ? And is it not sealed to many to-day ? The truth is that for the first time the causal and essentially rational type of mind had been joined in the same individual with those other qualities which impel to the pa- tient investigation of facts and details; rare combination, so success- fully repeated in the intellectual constitutions of Charles Darwin and Ernst Haeckel. When we compare, from our disinterested standpoint in America, the great chef d' oeuvre of Jean Lamarck, its systematic execution, its definite, avowed purpose, and its vast array of proofs from the only legitimate source of argument, with the various writings of Goethe containing his views on this subject, arranged with no sys- tematic order, having no well defined purpose, evincing no clear conception of nature’s means or methods, and manifesting a com- paratively scanty acquaintance with particular cases by which the laws under discussion are to be illustrated, we cannot fail to per- ceive, in the circumstance of Haeckel’s placing his own country- man before the son of a rival nation, in his estimate of the relative labors of the two pioneers of evolution, a trace of that almost inevitable national bias which lurks in regions of the brain inac- cessible to the invasion even of exact science. The essential incongruity between the first and last parts of the following passage will be apparent to all. “At the head of the French natural philosophy stands Jean Lamarck, who, in the history of the doc- trine of descent, next to Darwin and Goethe, occupies the first place. To him will remain the immortal glory of having for the first time brought forward the theory of descent as an independent scientific theory and established it as the natural philosophical foundation of all biology.” He certainly ascribes to Goethe no such “ im- mortal glory” as this. There is but one distinct element in Darwinism that is not also found in Lamarckism. This is the important recognition of the GENESIS OF MAN. law of competition among living organisms as a factor in develop- ment ; that principle which Darwin so forcibly expresses by the phrase “ struggle for existence.” Lamarck does indeed recognize this “ struggle ” and the influence it exerts in preventing the un- checked multiplication of any one species from rendering the globe uninhabitable to others. But he seems to regard this as a wise precaution and calculated “ to preserve all in the established order.” In other words, he recognizes it as a statical but not as a dynamical law. He fails to perceive its influence in transforming species. It is the full appreciation of this element that constitutes the real strength of Darwinism ; it is the key-stone of the arch of the descent theory, for the discovery and successful illustration of which too great praise cannot be awarded to the English naturalist. But every other important principle embraced in his Origin of Spe- cies was also contained in more or less definite form in the Philo- sophic Zoologique. The failure of Lamarck’s views to gain the ascendancy so rapidly attained by those of Darwin, was due to a variety of causes. First among these was the general fact that the state of science and pub- lic opinion had not, at his time, sufficiently advanced for the gen- eral reception of that class of ideas ; and any estimate of Lamarck’s works which leaves out their silent, leavening influence upon cer- tain classes directly, and thence indirectly upon society at large, is too hastily made and fails to do them justice. Next in impor- tance, in preventing the early spread of Lamarckism, comes the un- fortunate omission, above alluded to, to grasp the great law of bio- logical competion in its dynamic form. As a third influence may be ranked the somewhat direct and undiplomatic method of La- marck, which never consulted the policy of what he wished to say or courted the approval of high authorities. Every truth in his possession was put forward in the most direct and naked manner, re- gardless of the shock it might produce upon a world still groping in the murky atmosphere of teleology. Still a fourth element of weak- ness in the Lamarckian philosophy was the inadequate emphasis which he laid upon the most important of all his principles, that of heredity, and the correspondingly undue importance ascribed to habit, to use and disuse, as a direct agent in the modification of or- gans. The real failure here was to grasp the true connection and cooperation of these two principles. In short he seemed but dimly 14 GENESIS OF MAN. to perceive the manner in which the inheritance of slight variations, however produced, and their transmission to successive generations, brings about, in the course of time, the transformation of some, and the extinction of other species. It is the clear conception and forci- ble presentation of this principle and its happy combination with that of the perpetual competition going on in nature, that gives to Darwin’s exposition that air of extreme probability and that power of universal conviction so characteristic of his works. The importance of this distinction between the methods of the two naturalists in expressing this conception may justify me in borrowing a few very appropriate terms from the Biology of Her- bert Spencer for its better illustration. We may then say that while Lamarck seemed clearly to comprehend the influence of the environment (milieu) upon the organism, and to attribute the results to this as the one great and sufficient cause, he failed on the one hand to take in the full scope of the environment, and on the other to conceive of all the susceptibilities of the organism. In his conception of the former he inadequately, if at all, appreciated the organic element, the influence of one organism upon another ob- jectively considered as a modifying force. In his notion of the organism and its susceptibilities he laid too great stress upon the principle of “ direct equilibration,” and comparatively little upon the far more important one of “ indirect equilibration.” To the readers of the Philosophic Zoologique it seemed a crude, to many a ridiculous, explanation of the length of the fore-limbs and neck of the giraffe, that they had become elongated by perpetual attempts to reach the branches of trees that lay beyond the reach of other animals; and while he admits that this could not have been accomplished by the efforts of any single individual, and ascribes it to a series of cumulative efforts through many generations, thus clearly recog- nizing and expressly affirming the influence of heredity, he yet fails to show the way in which this influence must have been ex- erted, its modus operandi. He does not say, for example, that the great elongation referred to was initiated in some remote ancestor by some slight variation in this direction, either accidental or per- haps due to the animal’s efforts; that this variation, proving ad- vantageous and being transmitted to a numerous progeny, rendered their chances of survival in critical periods greater than those of such as possessed no such peculiarity; that this power of survival, GENESIS OF MAN. due to this inheritable peculiarity, became thus a constant force which, through the interbreeding of those possessing it, tended to increase this variation, until in the course of generations it resulted in differentiating the giraffe in the special attributes of length of cervical vertebra; and of anterior limbs, and in giving it its present anomalous position among antelopes. Instead of this, Lamarck says: “ With reference to habits it is curious to observe their results in the peculiar form and figure of the giraffe (camelo-pardalis). It is known that this animal, the tallest of the mammals, inhabits the interior of Africa, and that it lives in places where the earth, almost always arid and without herbage, compels it to browse upon the leaves of trees and to be continually exerting itself to reach them. From this habit, long maintained in all the individ- uals of its race, it has resulted that its fore-limbs have become longer than its hind ones, and that its neck has become so much elongated that the giraffe, without rearing upon its hind feet ele- vates its head and reaches to the height of six metres, (nearly twenty feet).”4 It will be observed how in this reasoning (and it is so throughout), Lamarck passes from the observed fact directly to the original cause, leaving out the intermediate steps which it is necessary to supply in order to conceive of the manner in which the results are produced. Now, it is precisely this part of the ar- gument that mankind in general require before they are willing to give in their adhesion to a theory. They say: “it all looks plau- sible enough, but you fail to show us how it actually takes place.” As in his illustrations, so in his general “ laws,” Lamarck fails to grasp the principle of Natural Selection. His first great law is expressed in these words : “ In every animal which has not passed the limit of its developments, the frequent and sustained use of any organ little by little strengthens, develops, and enlarges this organ, and gives it a power proportionate to the duration of this exercise; while the constant failure to use such organ insensibly enfeebles and deteriorates it, and progressively diminishes its capac- ities, causing it finally to disappear.”5 His second law is as fol- lows : “All that nature has caused individuals to acquire or lose through the influence of the circumstances to which their race has been long exposed, and consequently through the influence of the 4 Phil. Zoo., Tome I, p, 254. Paris, 1873. 5 Loc. cit., p. 235. GENESIS OF MAN. predominant exercise of any organ, or through that of a constant failure to exercise any part, it preserves through inheritance ( development of the human race. Here the cloaca is divided by a horizontal partition into two distinct orifices, both opening externally; nipples are formed on the mammae, to which the young attach themselves, and the clavicles are distinct from the sternum. In these respects, the marsupials agree with all the higher mammals. The distin- guishing character in which they differ from them, and that from which the name of the sub-class has been taken, is the existence of a remarkable pouch or sack (marsupium) on the under side of the female, in which the young are placed at a very early period, and there retained until they are able to take care of themselves. This pouch has been aptly likened to a second or supplementary uterus, and the marsupials have accordingly been called by some Didelphia. Our well-known opossum (Didelphys opossum) is our only North American representative; but in Australia, this group of animals constitutes the greater part of the mammalian fauna. The absence of a placenta is the only other important particular in which the marsupials differ from the higher mammals. Indeed, the marsupium seems to constitute a sort of substitute for a pla- centa, and the want of the latter may be regarded as the physio- logical cause of the development of the former. The monotremes, however, are without either, and those who know would do well to explain how these animals are able to dispense writh them both. The so-called true Mammalia all possess a fully developed pla- centa, and are therefore distinguished from the two groups last mentioned as forming a third sub-class, the Placeyitalia. This organ is of great importance in the classification of the higher mammals, its mode of attachment furnishing excellent and reliable general characters. In some, for example, the placenta is decidu- ous from the inner wall of the uterus, while in others it is not, and on this distinction is based the primary division of the whole sub- class into the Deciduata and the Indecidua. The latter are the least perfectly organized, and comprise the Edentata, the Cetacea, 56 GENESIS OF MAN. and the Ungulata. In man the placenta is deciduous, and he can therefore have descended from none of these. The Dcciduata again fall into two divisions according as the embryo is attached by the placenta to the uterus upon a single small area or disk, or by a band or girdle extending entirely around it. The former are called Discoplacentalia, the latter Zono- placentalia. The Zonoplacentalia embrace the Carnaria (Carnivora and Pinnipedia) and the Chelophora, to which the elephant belongs. The Discoplacentalia comprise the rodents, the Insectivora (moles, etc.), the Chiroptera (bats), the lemurs (Prosimiac), and the apes (Simiae). To this last legion, also, belongs man, who differs in this respect not at all from the mouse, mole, bat, lemur, of ape. Now it is a remarkable fact that in one order of the marsupials, the Pedimana, embracing the two families Chironectida and Didcl- phyida, to the last of which our opossum belongs, the hind feet are modified, in a peculiar way, into organs for grasping, resembling hands. This group can therefore only be regarded as exhibiting the earliest marks of that important course of transformation which culminated in the apes and in man. The course of develop- ment was from this group of marsupials directly to one within the Dcciduata. Leaving all other animals wholly out of its course, the line of descent of man passes immediately from the Marsupialia to the Prosimiac or lemur group, an order which Haeckel takes out of Blumenbach’s Qnadrumana, because it is so much farther sepa- rated from the other apes than any of these are from one another. They are ape-like creatures, but shade off in a very interesting way into nearly all the remaining orders of the Discoplacentalia. The Chiromys Madagascariensis forms the transition to the rodents; the Galeopithecus of the Sunda Islands, to the bats; the Macrotarsi, to the insectivora; and the Brachytarsi, particularly the Lori (,Stenops), to the true apes. They also exhibit close affinities to the Sloths (Bradipoda), which have been regarded as an order of the Edentata in the Indecidua; but recent investigations have proved that they have a deciduous placenta, and therefore it must be at this point that the Dcciduata and the Indecidua join. The lemurs are harmless and melancholy nocturnal animals of a graceful form, and are chiefly confined to the islands south of Asia and east of Africa, and particularly to Madagascar. Their frequency on the islands of the Indian Ocean led the English naturalist Sclater GENESIS OF MAN. 57 to name this once continental, but now mostly submerged region, Lemuria, a circumstance to which Haeckel has given special promi- nence, by pointing out the many facts which conspire to justify us in the conjecture that here may have existed the true “ cradle of the human race.” The lemurs form the eighteenth stage in the anthropogenetic line. From the lemurs to the true apes, the transition is comparatively easy. They evidently developed out of the Brachytarsi, the Ste- nops forming the nearest approach to a connecting link. Linnaeus, with almost prophetic ken, notwithstanding his dual- istic proclivites, classed man with the apes, lemurs, and bats, in his celebrated order, Primates. Blumenbach fancied he saw in the human foot a pretext for rescuing man from this association, and accordingly erected for him a separate order, which he called Bimana (two-handed), distinguishing the apes, etc., as Qnadru- mana (four-handed). This classification was adopted by Cuvier, and is the one which has generally prevailed among naturalists, down to Huxley and Haeckel. Huxley, however, gave the whole subject a complete re-investigation, and arrived at the conclusion that Blumenbach’s order Bimana cannot be maintained on anato- mical grounds. He shows, in the most convincing manner, that the distinctions alleged to exist between the posterior hands of apes and the feet of man are apparent only, that they were based on physiological and not on morphological considerations. The apes are just as good bimana as men are, and men are just as good quadrumana as the apes. In neither are the posterior limbs in all respects homologous to the anterior. The tarsal bones are differently arranged from the carpal bones, atnd there are three distinct muscles serving to move the foot that are wholly wanting in the hand. But all this is as true of the apes as of man. The limited opposability of the great toe in man is only a functional distinction. The muscles of opposability are all present; they are merely atrophied by disuse and adaptation to altered conditions. Traces of this power are found in many savages, who hold on with their toes to the branches of trees in the forests where they live, and otherwise employ this posterior thumb in a variety of ways which Europeans cannot imitate. There are, moreover, many instances on record of men acquiring extraordinary dexterity in the use of their toes. Every one in this country has seen the exhi- 58 GENESIS OF MAN. bitions of the armless man, who travelled through our towns and displayed marvellous feats performed with his toes. Again, infants make far more use of their great toes than adults do. Watch a new-born babe as it lies in its cradle and amuses itself with exer- cise of its muscular activities; compare the movements of its hands with those of its feet, and you cannot but be struck with the comparative indifference with which it manages both. The human foot, whose careful study has been said to constitute a sure cure for atheism, and whose wonderful adaptation to the purpose to which it is applied has been regarded as an unanswerable argument for the doctrine of design, can therefore be nothing more than a natural result of the modification of the posterior hand of the ape, in simple obedience to the mechanical law of adaptation to changed conditions, while in it are found all the visible elements of that ancestral organ which the equally monistic law of heredity has transmitted from our simian progenitors. Huxley, therefore, re- stores the Linnaean order Primates, removing only the Chiroptera. Haeckel, however, would adhere to his order Prosimiae, the lemurs, for the reasons above stated. The true apes are primarily divided into two great groups, which are as distinct geographically as they are anatomically. These are the Catarrkinac or Old World apes, and the Platyrrhinae, or New World monkeys. They differ chiefly in two important respects. The Platyrrhinae have a flat and broad nose, like other animals. The nostrils open outivardly, and are separated by a broad interval. They have, also, thirty-six teeth, eighteen in each jaw. In both these respects they differ from man. The Catarrhinae, on the other hand, have a somewhat projecting, laterally compressed, and often arched or aquiline nose, with the nostrils close together and opening downwards. They have only thirty-two teeth, or sixteen in each jaw. In both these respects they agree with man. The clear-cut, much projecting, and elegantly formed nose of the Nose- ape (Scmnopithecus nasicus) would adorn the face of any European nobleman, while the countenance, taken in its ensemble, of Cerco- pithecus pctaurista would be sure* to call to any one’s mind some not very bad-looking person of his own acquaintance. And yet these handsome apes are endowed with long tails. Not only is the number of the teeth of the Catarrhinae the same as in man, but they are distributed in precisely the same manner, namely:— GENESIS OF MAN. 59 four incisors, two canine or eye-teeth, and ten molars or grinders, in each jaw. The Catarrhinae are further divided into two groups of tail- bearing and tailless apes. The tail-bearing apes have most proba- bly been developed directly from the lemurs, and therefore con- stitute the nineteenth stage in the descent of man. Our ancient forefathers in this group were perhaps similar to the now living Semnopithccus, from which the tailless apes, forming the twentieth stage, were differentiated chiefly by the loss of their tail.. These latter bear the greatest resemblance to man, and are called anthro- poid apes, constituting the family Anthropoides. The family con- sists, as far as known, of but four genera, Hylobates, the Gibbon of southern Asia; Satyr us, the Orang of Borneo and the Sunda Islands; Engeco, the Chimpanzee of southern and western Africa, and the Gorilla, first discovered by the missionary Wilson, in 1847, on the Gaboon River, western Africa, and afterwards by Du Chaillu. The Gorilla is the largest of known apes, and exceeds the human stature. To none of these four anthropoid apes, however, can we point as being in all respects the nearest to man. The Gibbon resembles man most in the form of the thorax, the Orang in the development of the brain, the Chimpanzee in the formation of the skull, and the Gorilla in the differentiation of hand and foot, and also in the relative length of the arms. It is therefore evident that man can- not have descended directly from any known living ape. His real progenitor must, in a greater or less degree, have combined all these characters, and has no doubt been long extinct. It is from paleontology that we alone hope for aid in the discovery of this “missing link.” The fossil remains of this extinct genus (Pithecan- thropus) may be looked for with some confidence in the still little known . region of south-eastern Asia, the Malay Archipelago, and throughout central and western Africa. The comparative anatomy and osteology of these four genera of anthropoid apes have been exhaustively studied by Carl Vogt, Huxley, and others. The final cdnclusion to which Huxley comes, and which he expresses in the most unqualified and emphatic manner, is that no matter what system of organs we take, a com- parison of the modifications in the Catarrhine series leads to one and the same result: that the anatomical differences that distin- GENESIS OF MAN. guish man from the Orang, Gorilla or Chimpanzee, are not as great as those which distinguish these latter from the lower Catarrhinae (Cynoccphalus, Makako, Ccrcopithecus). Therefore, as Haeckel remarks, it is incorrect to say that man has descended from the apes; he is himself an ape, and belongs as strictly to the Catarrhine group as the Gorilla or the Orang-outang! He therefore estab- lishes another family within that group, together with the Anthro- poides, which he calls the Erecti or Anthropi. This family he divides into two genera, the first embracing the now extinct ances- tor of the human race, the Pithecanthropus or ape-man, which therefore forms the twenty-first genealogical stage, and the second being the genus Homo, or man as we find him, forming the twenty- second and last stage in his development from the moner. Three anatomical distinctions of any importance are all that exist to separate the two families Anthropoides and Anthropi. One is the more erect posture of the latter—a difference of degree, however, which varies both with the apes and with men. The second is the higher brain development of the latter, which is also only a quantitative distinction. The third and only distinction which can be called qualitative, is the differentiation in the An- thropi of the larynx into an organ of speech. And not even this much can now be fairly said, since it is found that the larynx of monkeys exhibits a much higher state of development than that of other animals.10 Haeckel, however, regards Pithecanthropus as a speechless man, having the erect posture and differentiated brain, but who had not yet acquired the power of articulate language, or the necessary organs for its utterance. For this reason he offers also a synonym for his name Pithecanthropus, the equally appro- priate one, Alalus, the speechless. This, however, is only theory. In point of fact, the erect posture, size and quality of brain, forma- tion of vocal cords, and the origin of articulate speech, must have all advanced pari passu, mutually promoting one another, and developing by insensible degrees, according to the universal method of all nature. To the various races of men as recognized by ethnologists, Haeckel, in harmony with his general system, gives the rank of species of the genus Homo. All definitions of the term species 10 Emile Blanchard, “ Voice in Man and Animals,” in Popular Science Monthly, September, 1876, page 519. GENESIS OF MAN. 61 having failed to unite upon any absolutely constant character as a condition to its application, the use of it here is justifiable, not- withstanding the ease with which the human races hybridize, and no matter what theory may be preferred of their origin or rela- tionships. Of these species he makes out twelve, and advances an interesting theory of their origin and geographical distribution over the globe; but upon this new field we can here follow him no farther. In casting a retrospective glance over the vast subject thus hastily passed in review, there are a few salient points which will have most probably, in an especial manner, struck the mind of the reader. One of these is likely to be the great brevity of the anthropo- genetic line,—considering the variety and multiplicity of living forms found on the globe. We perceive that of the seven sub- kingdoms of animals now recognized, only three are touched by it, viz ;—the Protozoa, Worms, and Vertebrates. The zoophytes, echinoderms, anthropods, and mollusks all branch off either below or at the worm stage, and the transition from the Tunicata, a worm-form, is direct to the vertebrata. This, when adequately appreciated, is an astonishing fact, and one which would never have been conjectured but for positive anatomical evidences. Those who believed in a law of development were looking vainly for proof of the derivation of the different types one out of anoth- er, and discussing which should be considered lowest, the articu- lates or the mollusks. They expected to find proof of a series with the radiates at the bottom and the vertebrates at the top. The truth, as it has at last dawned upon us, dispenses with all such speculations. Equally surprising is the shortness and directness of the transi- tion from the lowest to the highest vertebrates, from the Amphi- oxus to the Ape. All the vague surmises of some extensive course of descent and lineal relationship among the numerous classes and orders of vertebrates are now also brought to an end. The higher fishes and higher amphibians, the reptiles and the birds, are all left to pursue special routes of their own; and a brief series of easy and rapid transitions through the lowest fish-form, the Selachia, and the lowest amphibian-forms, the Sozobranchia and Sozura, brings us at once to the lowest mammalian stage. 62 GENESIS OF MAN. But perhaps the most surprising part of this whole course is its one great stride through the entire mammalian class, from the marsupial to the lemur. All vain expectations of finding some thread of relationship that should lead through the labyrinth of varied mammalian orders, and connect us with the horse, the dog, the elephant, etc., are thus happily set at rest, and we are permitted only to claim such consanguineal relationship with the opossum, the lemur and the ape. In fact, instead of a long concatenated “chains animals S as La- marck supposes, the animal kingdom presents rather a tree, spread- ing from very near the base with almost a whorl of unequal branches or subordinate trunks, each of which is again variously branched, giving the whole the form of an inverted cone or pyra- mid. At the upper extremity of each of these branches, which have come a long way independently of each other, is found one of the great groups or types of now living creatures, man occupy- ing the highest summit of the vertebrate branch. Contemplating now the great number of branches that arise at different points, some of which are short and apparently stunted, while others push upward with different degrees of vigor, only one or two reaching truly lofty and commanding positions, the thought forcibly strikes us that this picture reveals the universal tendency of Nature to develop organic forms. We realize that this vital force or nisus is constantly pressing at every point, but that as the conditions of life are limited, success is possible only at a few points; that in consequence of obstacles of many kinds, not the least of which are offered by organic conditions themselves that have pre-occupied the field, the degree of success at these points varies widely, and produces all grades of vigor, size, length, and ramification among the branches. The highest and most thrifty branches mark the line of absolutely least resistance; the shorter and less vigorous ones indicate lines offering varied degrees of resistance; while the stunted, dwarfed, and retrograde branches show lines of resistance so great that the vital force barely over- comes it. Finally, all points from which no buds or branches arise teach us over how large a proportion of nature the resisting agencies wholly overbalance the organic tendencies, and no life can originate. Another thought to which the attentive contemplation of this GENESIS OE MAN- 63 theme gives rise, is the greater antecedent probability of like organs, occurring in different animals, being homologous, than of their being analogous. The conditions in which life finds itself placed are so infinitely variable, that the chances are almost infinity to one against the development of the same organ independently at two different times and places. Where the same organ is unex- pectedly found in two animals which had not been supposed to be at all related, it affords the strongest evidence that they are either immediately connected by blood, or at least that they have both descended from a common ancestor that possessed that organ. Hence the irresistible force of the testimony afforded by the so- called “ rudimentary organs,” which none but those who realize this important law can properly appreciate. That analogues do sometimes occur, in obedience to the law of adaptation, cannot, however, be denied; but they usually betray their origin by being formed on an essentially different principle, though in such a man- ner as to accomplish the same purpose. The wings of birds, bats, and insects are such cases of analogy, in each of which the morpho- logical differentiation is wholly different, while the physiological function is the same. The beak of the Ornithorhynchus is perhaps as near an approach as we have to a true morphological analogue, the descent of that animal from the birds being overruled by a preponderance of evidence against it. It is this principle, too, which conclusively negatives the pre- sumption which some have advanced, that the aborigines of America may have descended from the New World monkeys. Catarrhine man could never have sprung from a Platyrrhine ape. It is, moreover, this same biological law which justifies Haeckel in the assumption of so many hypothetical and long-extinct ances- tral forms, although no warrant for them is afforded by paleonto- logy. The Gastraea, the Chordonium, the Protamnion, the Pro- mammalia, and the Pithecanthropus are all creatures, not of his imagination, but of stern logic, based on a profound familiarity with all the facts and principles that bear upon the problem. The common origin and blood relationship of all creatures that possess a spinal column, of all that are endowed with five-toed feet, of all that develop an amnion, of all that have the double occipital con- dyle, of all that suckle their young, of all having the fore and hind feet differentiated into hands, of all that have the catarrhine nose 64 GENESIS OF MAN. and identical dentition—these are propositions whose demonstra- tion, by the aid of the law of heredity, is as complete and absolute as that of any proposition in Euclid. There is no other way to account for these facts. The chances of these organs being so many independent morphological analogues, produced by adapta- tion to identical conditions, are but as one to infinity. Either the dualistic conception of teleological design, i. e., mira- cle, must be admitted, or else there is no alternative from this ex- planation.