HISTORY „\N[> IJI11IA )S( )IM I A' OF MEDICAL JURISPRUDENCE. BY JOHN ORDRONAUX, PROFESSOR OF MEDICAL JURISPRUDENCE IN COLUMBIA COLLEGE, NEW YORK. HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF MEDICAL JURISPRUDENCE * BY JOHN ORDRONAUX, PROFESSOR OF MEDICAL JURISPRUDENCE IN COLUMBIA COLLEGE, NEW YORK. In approaching the philosophy of any science, the mind is at first bewildered by the multitudinous re- lations under which it presents itself. Aside from abstract principles, which are few and easily recognized, the variety of their application, the subtle forms under which they exhibit themselves, and the gradual blend- ing of their operations into each other, render their practical investigation always a difficult subject to mas- ter. Hence it is that we are driven to the common ground of accepted definition for the ttov otu whence to originate all study and successful investigation. This is particularly the case in the physical sciences, where a natural correlation knits them together in a chain of mutual dependencies. But when, overpowering all these correlations, the law undertakes to apply her canons to the admeasurement of civil wrongs growing out of the operation of physical agencies, then it is that the subject, by additional complication, becomes difficult of solution. We need at such a time a knowledge not simply of positive, instituted law, but of natural law; a knowledge not of the language of human enactments alone, but of the language of physical agents as they express themselves through pathological signs. With- out descending into metaphysical speculations, or losing *From the Am. Journal of Insanity for October, 1868. 2 ourselves in the mazes of dogmatic conjecture, it is still necessary that we should begin our inquiry with first principles—the germinal points—of every science. Hav- ing done this we can afterwards trace with ease and increasing success, the relations which flow out of them; for no science can be difficult to him who has thoroughly mastered its elements. It is not proposed, however, to enter into any large or critical discussion of the entire field before us, since that would indeed necessitate a volume of indefinite proportions. Medical jurisprudence as a science, is too comprehensive a department of philosophy to be dis- posed of in a magazine article. Its boundary lines exceed those even of natural history, since, as a syncre- tism between natural and human laws, it covers the entire field of both territories. Those who look at it only as the caudal fin to chairs of obstetrics or chemistry in medical colleges, know little of it besides its name. To them it is simply a myth, imported into the curriculum of medical study by way of ornament alone. Yet if we may trust one whose life was chiefly spent in its cul- tivation, and who may be supposed to have known all that proficiency in it cost him, as it will any one, desiring to follow its myriad avenues of necessitated investiga- tion,—if we may quote the language of the distinguished Fodere, we shall need advance no better argument, nor could we adduce a stronger one, in behalf of its ma- jestic proportions. Let us listen to the great master, as he utters in liis introduction, these striking words: “ Si V on porte an reste a ce sujet toute V attention pul il merite, Von ne pourra pul etre effraye de V immensite des connaissances qV exige V exercise legitime de la Medecine Legale /”—and if we pause but to reflect upon the fact that this neglected science, only tolerated by sufferance, and hardly adopted into the sisterhood of studies in medical schools, nor often granted a separate altar and 3 an ordained priesthood—that this humble department includes anatomy, physiology, pathology, therapeutics, surgery, chemistry, botany and hygiene as its medical phasis; while with a still wider range, and regarding man as living a life of relation and responsibility towards his fellow-beings in society, it enters into the vast cham- bers of law, there to consider and weigh the testamentary capacity of parties; their mental ability to form con- tracts of whatever name or nature; the rules regulating survivorship and life assurance; the physical compe- tency underlying the domestic relations, and determining not only the rights of the actually living, but of their posterity; and lastly, criminal responsibility as affected by insanity or intoxication;—if we go no further than these facts, we shall be convinced, at the threshold of any inquiry into its philosophy, that no one can over- estimate or over-state the comprehensiveness of this field of multifarious investigation. But law and medicine, although uniting in the pro- duction of this third science, cannot be said to hold a divided empire over its practice; for law alone is, and must ever be, the supreme arbiter of human actions in society, nor can she surrender her authority over the temporal accountability of mankind without at the same time surrendering her life and her essential pre- rogatives. The application of medical jurisprudence to the admeasurement of physical facts affecting the civil or criminal responsibility of parties, amounts practically only to this—that medicine furnishes the lights of her experience, and law applies them according to the es- tablished rules of her tribunals, and as modified by the equities of each particular case. Thus the aid of medi- cine is often invoked; she is even at times intrusted with the scales; but law always retains the sword, always retains the right of reviewing the judgement and prescribing the penalty. And this is but just, 4 since it leaves either science to perform its destined part in the economy of human government: law, as the heavenly appointed governor of man in society; defining what is right and prohibiting what is wrong; protecting the weak and compelling the powerful; scrutinizing the state of the mind, together with the intention, as the foundation of all human responsibility; deliberate and merciful in her judgments, swift and terrible in her punishment: and, on the other hand, medicine, walking- like a Good Samaritan with the oil and balsam of phi- lanthropy in her hand; guiding hood-winked justice whenever she explores the dark valleys of bodily or mental infirmity, and striving to mitigate the too rigor- ous application of legal canons, whenever weakness is mistaken for error, and disease is mistaken for crime. HISTORY OF MEDICAL JURISPRUDENCE. Before proceeding to investigate tlie philosophy of a science of such vast proportions, it may not be amiss to indulge in a brief retrospect of its history. That any- thing like a perfected system of forensic medicine, whose principles are founded upon the laws of our physical being, should have been completely formed be- fore those fundamental laws were themselves discovered, is not to be believed. To speak of it, therefore, as an established science before the labors of Harvey, Vesa- lius, or Fallopius had broken the seals of rational anat- omy, is to confound the narrow results of ancient observation with the grander explorations of modern times. The human mind, powerful and penetrating as it may be in research; reflective and logical as it may show itself in tracing analogies and elucidating princi- ples, cannot erect systems by its solitary fiat. These are the offspring only of centuries, the accumulated labor of generations, each receiving, transporting, and in its turn transmitting the torch of learning to its sue* cessor, and thus, little by little, building islands and continents in the great sea of human thought. Nevertheless, one very important branch of medical jurisprudence was unquestionably recognized and pro- vided for in the legislation of antiquity; and this branch which was founded in that first of governing principles, the law of self-preservation, formed a true system of medical police even among the Israelites and the Hindoos. The frequent lustrations and isolations of the person, enjoined as part of the ceremonial law among those nations, converted a physiological safe- guard against contagion into an act of worship, in this wise insuring its daily practice by all classes in the com- munity. And so urgent was the necessity of personal purification deemed among a population proverbially unclean, and in a climate disposing to pestilence, that the Mohammedan was ordered to cleanse himself with sand wherever water was not to be had. From this incorporation of sanitary observances into the religion of the country, it followed that priests became the ear- liest custodians of public health, and it may be truly said, the earliest medical jurists on record. Their edu- cation, which was of the most extensive character pos- sible at that day, included a thorough knowledge of medicine as then understood; and they were well qual- ified, therefore, to act as a sanitary police. They defined the civil status of the citizen by first defining his relig- ious and ceremonial condition. If pure in body—then might he go at large into the streets of the market places—the temple or the synagogue; and contrariwise if impure, he was at once put under civil disability and isolation. Even at this day, in India, caste, rank, is forfeited by touching articles forbidden in the religious code, and the priest among the Hindoos is still in many senses the acknowledged lawgiver, as in ages past. These were certainly wise enactments for those days 6 of little knowledge, and well suited to tliat population among whom the source of filth has been at all times inbred and irrevocable. They show too that hygiene is the earliest study, as it is the earliest necessity of man- kind in society; and in appointing the priesthood to the guardianship of public health, they gave them con- trol over one of the chief sources of public misery— destitution, vice and crime. When we peruse the laws of those nations living, as it were, in the gray dawn of time, and without the elevating advantages of inter- communication with other peoples: working out, with no inherited models of legislation, and no established codes of scientific truth, the great problem of national prosperity—when we see them promulgating laws whose wisdom seems far in advance of the civilization which gave them birth—laws whose outlines we cannot ex- pand, all our multiform and wonderful discoveries only serving to contribute details and formulae for their better and more economic administration—we cannot doubt that the scholarship of that day, as represented in its legislation, was something more than history has found materials with which to describe it. If the Israelites or the Egyptians could have laws enforced among them regulating marriage and the relations of the sexes—distinguishing between mortal and danger- ous wounds in order to affix penalties—and prescribing modes of embalming and interring the dead—thus in- volving some of the most important questions in the sanitary police of communities, we must surely believe that they fully comprehended the necessities of such regulations to be founded in the laws of our physical being—in a word, that their legislators must have been physicians. And, we need not ask, after reading the ordinances of Lycurgus, or the physical rubrics laid down by Pythagoras and Plato, whether they too had studied the laws of our bodily life. 7 There is no evidence, however, that any union of the professions of law and medicine in any one science and as a branch of jurisprudence was contemplated by the more cultivated Greeks. Except in questions of medical police, medical men were not often consulted by the tribunals of Greece. In that country the chief concern of legislation was to secure a robust people, capable of bearing arms, and in their prevalent ideas as to the best mode of perfecting the human species, they were led to the barbarous and unscientific practice of destroying delicate, and rearing only strong infants. To perfect this dogma of their political economy, and to provide for the health of cities and camps by assuaging the virulence of epidemic diseases, formed about the whole scope of Greek state medicine. For, aside from the admirable treatise on Air, Water and Locality, left us by the father of medicine—a treatise which still in- fluences the civilized world—no other contribution to the literature of that subject has come down to us. Whatever may have been the limited achievements of those days in forensic medicine, the opinions of Hippoc- rates and Aristotle upon certain physiological problems relating to the perpetuation of the species, have always carried with them an authoritative influence, not only in the schools, but with legislators, which succeeding ages have hardly extirpated. Many of the principles of the Canon Law, as formerly recognized in the Ec- clesiastical Courts of Europe, were undoubtedly founded upon the crude speculations of these authors, and in par- ticular of the Stagirite, whose Organon was the Bible of the schools of philosophy down to the time of Bacon. But when we pass to Borne, we meet at once the spirit of her truest grandeur in the superior character of her legislation. As early as the reign of good king Numa, a law was enacted which was intended to pro- 8 tect the life of the heir, by requiring medical assistance in critical cases.* And even before that auspicious day which saw the mighty lawyers of Justinian remodeling the jurisprudence of their country, the law of the Twelve Tables had made provisions of the wisest and most humane character in relation to the civil rights of pos- terity. The Romans who had imported their laws, as they had their arts from Greece, were almost exclusively guided in their legislation by the dictum of ancient philosophers; hence they very naturally incorporated into their jurisprudence the best models of morality and polity which their age afforded. Masters of the world, they readily subsidized its treasures, whether of art or philosophy, to the aggrandizement of their own glory, and the perpetuation of their own empire. Yet such was the petrified adherence of the age to the canons of the old masters; so much was it the rule to swear by established and mouldy authority—a custom whose practice even in the middle ages and among the school- men silenced every objection with the simple sic magister dixit—that in the Pandects of Justinian, where various titlesf are created referring to crimes, physical de- formities and questions of legitimacy, the courts were instructed not to be governed by the evidence of living physicians, (who might be most competent to explain particular points then at issue,) but to form their opinions exclusively propter auctoritatem doctissimi Hippocratis. Yet the creation of an archiater,% or state * This was the Lex Regia “ De Inferendo Mortuo,” forbidding the burial of a pregnant woman until the foetus should first have been extracted.—Digest: Lib. II., Tit. 8. f These titles are uDe Statu Ilominum, De Sicariis et Veneficis; De Inspiciendo Ventre, &e.; De Hermaphroditism De Impotentia, &c., &c. Instit.: Lib. 4, Tit. 18. X Code Theodos.: 12, 13. 9 physician, whose public functions corresponded to those of a modern health officer, who was himself court phy- sician, and the acknowledged head of the medical pro- fession, must have imparted to his opinions great weight with the judges, notwithstanding the institutional rev- erence for Hippocrates. And possibly his influence was not unwisely exercised over some of his royal patients, since we find an occasional relaxation in the rigorous construction of statutes, sanctioned by imperial edicts. If we may credit Tacitus, the bodies of German- icus and Agricola were medically examined, and in the former slight traces of poison were noticed; but whether the autopsy was undertaken at the command of some tribunal and as forming a part of a judicial inquisition, does not appear.* In the confusion which followed the irruption of the barbarians and the downfall of the Koman Empire, we lose sight for a while of the workings of municipal regulations. The larger operations of war, conquest, and the foundation of new governments, overshadow all other considerations, and it is not until order once more reigns, and the thoughts of men can be concentrated upon the necessities of a system of jurisprudence, that we may expect to find the tamer studies of philosophy and legislation fixing their attention. In the whirlwind of savage customs which ruled society throughout west- ern Europe during the dark ages, legal medicine could hope for no positive recognition. Its very sources were ignored, and its principles derided as a sacrilegious at- tempt to invade the secret haunts of nature; and in its stead ordeals by fire, water, or the judicial combat were introduced, as so many direct interrogations of the Deity. But the law's of a country, like its language, are not easily extirpated even by conquest; and it seldom hap- *Tac. Annal. Lib. 2, 13, and Suetonius in vita Caliguloe, § 1. 10 pens tliat tlie civil legislation of a conqueror escapes the infection of local customs and language. For it is always easier to adopt a system of laws than to frame one, and the proud jurisprudence of Rome was of too practical as well as philosophical a character to permit of its easy overthrow by barbarian codes. Hence, the wiser con- querors were not slow in availing themselves of this fountain of justice. They drew largely from it, nor did they ever cease paying that homage to the laws of Rome which they had so emphatically denied to her Empire. It would not be difficult to show that the Roman law had authorized the calling and consultation of physicians before courts in difficult cases, and finding the same rule prevailing in the jurisprudence of the Ostrogoths, in Italy,* and of Charlemagne,f in France, it is easy to conjecture the source whence the rule was derived. This brief sketch may be said to include the whole aspect of legal medicine as presented to us in the laws and legislation of antiquity. That it made but little progress—that it should have been extremely desultory in its application, and should have continued a weak and inferior adjuvant to courts—will be readily under- stood when we reflect that most of the physical sciences upon which rests its foundations, and whence its true life is drawn, had scarcely risen upon the horizon of human thought. No Harvey had yet shown that blood circulated through the arteries, instead of air. No Vesalius had yet established a rational system of anat- omy based upon positive demonstration. No Boerliaave or Van Helmont had yet explored the mine of chemistry, * Tlieodoric, their King, delegated the care of justice to consular s, correctors, and presidents, who, says Gibbon, “ governed the fifteen regions of Italy according to the principles, and even the forms of Roman jurisprudence.” Roman Empire, vol. 4, p. 21. •[Capitularies, 116, lib. 7. 11 through which Priestly and Lavoisier were destined to descend into the very penetralia of matter. Man’s nature was still a sealed book, before which flcimen and augur and oracle stood dumb, and over which law herself ministered with scarcely any knowledge of its contents. Whatever, therefore, may have been her errors, they were, at most, only the reflected errors of her day and generation; nor should those things be imputed to her as crimes which were done under sanction of the highest authority she could summon, and the fullest measure of light she could obtain. It is generally admitted that the application of medical knowledge to jurisprudence, and the practical recog- nition of a science of forensic medicine, only commenced about the middle of the sixteenth century. The criminal code of the Germanic Empire, originating with Charles V., and enacted by the Diet held at Eatisbon, in 1532, (Constitiitio Criminalis Carolina) is the first public recognition and the first legal application of the science which we meet with in modern history. This celebrated code, which still rules the proceedings of German Courts, enacts that physicians shall be con- sulted in all cases where death has been occasioned by violent means, whether criminal or accidental,